Principia. Innovative papers in philosophy and social sciences
The journal publishes original papers in philosophy and sociology.
Make a submissionThe journal publishes original papers in philosophy and sociology.
Make a submissionInnovative papers in philosophy and social sciences
Description
Principia. Innovative papers in philosophy and social sciences is a journal of the Institute of Philosophy, Jagiellonian University of Krakow. It has been published continuously since 1990. The journal publishes original papers in philosophy and sociology.
ISSN: 0867-5392
eISSN: 2084-3887
MNiSW points: 40
UIC ID: 200289
DOI: 10.4467/20843887PI
Editorial team
Affiliation
Jagiellonian University in Kraków
Publication date: 2024
Editor-in-Chief (since 2022): Marek Drwięga
Jacek Migasiński, Maciej Kałuża, Radosław Strzelecki
Principia, Vol. 71 (2024), First view (2024)
Jacek Migasiński, Maciej Kałuża, Radosław Strzelecki
Principia, Vol. 71 (2024), First view (2024)
Publication date: 21.12.2023
Editor-in-Chief: Marek Drwięga
The publication was financed by the Jagiellonian University in Kraków – Institute of Philosphy.
Claude Romano
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 5 - 45
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.001.19380Michael Staudigl
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 47 - 70
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.002.19381Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 71 - 130
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.003.19382The aim of the paper is to interpret Jean-Luc Marion’s phenomenology of donation as a unique philosophical theory of performance. The inspirations, direction and context of the presented interpretation delimit the main transformations occurring within the contemporary humanities, shaped by the numerous countertextual turns. Presented here are the main themes of Marion’s phenomenology of donation, such as countermethod, gift, sacrament, revelation, givenness, occurrence, contingency, saturated phenomenon, witness, etc., in the hope of finding performative instructions in them. The article is concluded with a multi-faceted critique of Marion’s phenomenology of donation to show why it is not tenable and must give way to the phenomenological principle of performance.
Michał Maczuga
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 131 - 160
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.004.19383The purpose of this paper is to examine two issues – that of the alien and of violence – within the framework of responsive phenomenology proposed by Bernhard Waldenfels. The author demonstrates how each of these phenomena necessitate a radicalized version of phenomenological reduction – a responsive reduction. This helps us understand the essential significance that problems of the alien and of violence play in Waldenfels’ responsive ethics.
Mateusz Waśko
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 161 - 174
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.005.19384Stefano Micali, Adriana J. Mickiewicz
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 175 - 186
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.006.19385Claude Romano
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 5 - 45
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.001.19380Michael Staudigl
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 47 - 70
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.002.19381Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 71 - 130
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.003.19382The aim of the paper is to interpret Jean-Luc Marion’s phenomenology of donation as a unique philosophical theory of performance. The inspirations, direction and context of the presented interpretation delimit the main transformations occurring within the contemporary humanities, shaped by the numerous countertextual turns. Presented here are the main themes of Marion’s phenomenology of donation, such as countermethod, gift, sacrament, revelation, givenness, occurrence, contingency, saturated phenomenon, witness, etc., in the hope of finding performative instructions in them. The article is concluded with a multi-faceted critique of Marion’s phenomenology of donation to show why it is not tenable and must give way to the phenomenological principle of performance.
Michał Maczuga
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 131 - 160
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.004.19383The purpose of this paper is to examine two issues – that of the alien and of violence – within the framework of responsive phenomenology proposed by Bernhard Waldenfels. The author demonstrates how each of these phenomena necessitate a radicalized version of phenomenological reduction – a responsive reduction. This helps us understand the essential significance that problems of the alien and of violence play in Waldenfels’ responsive ethics.
Mateusz Waśko
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 161 - 174
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.005.19384Stefano Micali, Adriana J. Mickiewicz
Principia, Volume 70, 2023, pp. 175 - 186
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.23.006.19385Publication date: 21.12.2020
Editor-in-Chief: Marek Drwięga
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 5 - 22
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.001.17312Taking the 20th century Czech philosopher Jan Patočka as an example, in this paper, the author would like to illustrate the problem of human freedom when dealing with two kinds of experiences: war and political violence, as exemplified by the totalitarian state. Indeed, it is possible to treat these two types of experiences as historical experiences of evil. What is at stake, then, is the juxtaposition of human freedom and evil. Given this context, the Czech thinker sought to answer the question: in such a situation, with which moral response can or should one reply? When experiencing evil, how can or should a person behave?
Janusz A. Majcherek
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 23 - 36
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.002.17313The aggression of Putin’s Russia towards Ukraine has posed a dramatic challenge to the noble doctrine of non-violence. In line with an argument made in the 1980s by anti-Soviet Russian dissident Vladimir Bukovsky, war is not the opposite of peace; instead, violence is. Armed resistance, or warfare, is sometimes necessary to stop violence. According to Clausewitz, military aggression is insufficient to evoke a state of war; in its place, it is necessary to oppose aggression, i.e., actively mount a defense by the attacked party, thereby avoiding war requires not resisting the aggressor. However, the aggression against Ukraine broke two tenets of warfare: ius ad bellum and ius in bello. According to Michael Walzer’s typology, it is an unjust war waged by unjust methods, so resisting it, including militarily, amounts to waging a just war. According to Slavoj Žižek’s analysis, this establishes an ethically clear situation: evil is easily identifiable, and opposing it is an ethical duty. According to the philosopher Étienne Balibar, pacifism is not an option in such a situation.
Michał Bohun
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 37 - 55
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.003.17314This essay attempts to weigh in on the problem of evil in politics. The starting point follows the political reflections of B. Pascal and M. Montaigne. Here, the history of philosophy is used to conceptualize the problems of the present and, in fact, those that are enduring. Thinking about the sources of power and a state’s legitimacy proves to be a universal meditation on human destiny and freedom when challenged by existential threats.
Radosław Strzelecki
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 57 - 75
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.004.17315This paper aims to equally pinpoint the philosophical origins of Martin Heidegger’s entry into the Nazi movement and the thinker’s subsequent break with political involvement. Heidegger’s path to and from National Socialism should be apprehended not only through the philosopher’s biography but, above all, within the broader framework of the process of the development of his understanding of politics as an area of being set apart and accommodated by Western metaphysics, which marks the fulfillment of the essence of metaphysics as a forgetting of being. Heidegger’s philosophy has been repeatedly diagnosed (cf., e.g., Löwith, Adorno) as deeply linked to the fascist worldview; the line of reasoning taken up in this paper insists, on the contrary, on the integrity of the ethical reasoning behind Heidegger’s work, which emphasizes, concerning politics, its character of exploiting being, in the same way as it uniformizes people and transforms them into a resource. The conclusion, therefore, reveals the profoundly anti-fascist overtones of Heidegger’s writings from 1936–1946 and, simultaneously, underscores a worrying indifference to Heidegger’s relationship to totalitarian and non-totalitarian political systems.
Leszek Augustyn
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 77 - 105
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.005.17316Proceeding from a metaphorical (figurative) account of the problem of evil, and based on Leszek Kołakowski’s selected thoughts, this paper’s considerations aim to deliberate on “evil in politics” in the spirit of the shortcomings and excesses of freedom: namely, the lure of autocratic and totalitarian power. At issue is how the bounds of freedom are anthropologically and politically transgressed at the expense (to the point of abolishing) the freedom of others.
Weronika Plińska
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 107 - 136
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.006.17317In the article, I try to demonstrate that artistic photography which involves the use of technology of creating “shimmering, synthetic appearances” (K. Linker, “On Artificiality”) can become a medium for community art projects developed with people who are systemically excluded from view in the public sphere. Applying the method of iconographic analysis, I describe selected portrait photographs by Krzysztof Marchlak that feature images of people who belong to the Polish LGBTQ community. I draw in conclusion upon the artist’s large-format photographic panorama Paradiso, which I interpret as a socially engaged, “shimmering, synthetic appearance” of an artificial paradise for people expelled from the kingdom of binary gender oppositions.
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 5 - 22
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.001.17312Taking the 20th century Czech philosopher Jan Patočka as an example, in this paper, the author would like to illustrate the problem of human freedom when dealing with two kinds of experiences: war and political violence, as exemplified by the totalitarian state. Indeed, it is possible to treat these two types of experiences as historical experiences of evil. What is at stake, then, is the juxtaposition of human freedom and evil. Given this context, the Czech thinker sought to answer the question: in such a situation, with which moral response can or should one reply? When experiencing evil, how can or should a person behave?
Janusz A. Majcherek
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 23 - 36
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.002.17313The aggression of Putin’s Russia towards Ukraine has posed a dramatic challenge to the noble doctrine of non-violence. In line with an argument made in the 1980s by anti-Soviet Russian dissident Vladimir Bukovsky, war is not the opposite of peace; instead, violence is. Armed resistance, or warfare, is sometimes necessary to stop violence. According to Clausewitz, military aggression is insufficient to evoke a state of war; in its place, it is necessary to oppose aggression, i.e., actively mount a defense by the attacked party, thereby avoiding war requires not resisting the aggressor. However, the aggression against Ukraine broke two tenets of warfare: ius ad bellum and ius in bello. According to Michael Walzer’s typology, it is an unjust war waged by unjust methods, so resisting it, including militarily, amounts to waging a just war. According to Slavoj Žižek’s analysis, this establishes an ethically clear situation: evil is easily identifiable, and opposing it is an ethical duty. According to the philosopher Étienne Balibar, pacifism is not an option in such a situation.
Michał Bohun
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 37 - 55
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.003.17314This essay attempts to weigh in on the problem of evil in politics. The starting point follows the political reflections of B. Pascal and M. Montaigne. Here, the history of philosophy is used to conceptualize the problems of the present and, in fact, those that are enduring. Thinking about the sources of power and a state’s legitimacy proves to be a universal meditation on human destiny and freedom when challenged by existential threats.
Radosław Strzelecki
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 57 - 75
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.004.17315This paper aims to equally pinpoint the philosophical origins of Martin Heidegger’s entry into the Nazi movement and the thinker’s subsequent break with political involvement. Heidegger’s path to and from National Socialism should be apprehended not only through the philosopher’s biography but, above all, within the broader framework of the process of the development of his understanding of politics as an area of being set apart and accommodated by Western metaphysics, which marks the fulfillment of the essence of metaphysics as a forgetting of being. Heidegger’s philosophy has been repeatedly diagnosed (cf., e.g., Löwith, Adorno) as deeply linked to the fascist worldview; the line of reasoning taken up in this paper insists, on the contrary, on the integrity of the ethical reasoning behind Heidegger’s work, which emphasizes, concerning politics, its character of exploiting being, in the same way as it uniformizes people and transforms them into a resource. The conclusion, therefore, reveals the profoundly anti-fascist overtones of Heidegger’s writings from 1936–1946 and, simultaneously, underscores a worrying indifference to Heidegger’s relationship to totalitarian and non-totalitarian political systems.
Leszek Augustyn
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 77 - 105
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.005.17316Proceeding from a metaphorical (figurative) account of the problem of evil, and based on Leszek Kołakowski’s selected thoughts, this paper’s considerations aim to deliberate on “evil in politics” in the spirit of the shortcomings and excesses of freedom: namely, the lure of autocratic and totalitarian power. At issue is how the bounds of freedom are anthropologically and politically transgressed at the expense (to the point of abolishing) the freedom of others.
Weronika Plińska
Principia, Volume 69, Polityka i zło, 2022, pp. 107 - 136
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.22.006.17317In the article, I try to demonstrate that artistic photography which involves the use of technology of creating “shimmering, synthetic appearances” (K. Linker, “On Artificiality”) can become a medium for community art projects developed with people who are systemically excluded from view in the public sphere. Applying the method of iconographic analysis, I describe selected portrait photographs by Krzysztof Marchlak that feature images of people who belong to the Polish LGBTQ community. I draw in conclusion upon the artist’s large-format photographic panorama Paradiso, which I interpret as a socially engaged, “shimmering, synthetic appearance” of an artificial paradise for people expelled from the kingdom of binary gender oppositions.
Publication date: 21.12.2021
Editor-in-Chief: Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Giulia Cirillo
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 5 - 26
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.001.18691
It is easy to fall for a conceptual beauty and simplicity of the coherence theory of truth. But the texts in which its foundations were for the first time explicitly developed are rich in subtleties, defying a consistent interpretation and inviting various forms of criticism. That is why the following study will take one more look at the writings of Harold H. Joachim and Brand Blanshard, in order to prove that in the analyses which they proposed there is an additional, so far unrecognised element – namely the process of translation – which plays a crucial role in making their accounts valid and complete. Initially then, the article will specify how the notion of translation should be here understood. Next, key postulates of both theories will be recalled, with an indication of several potential inconsistencies which they might entail. Finally, the analysis exposes translative ground of each reconstructed model.
What will be thereby underscored, is not only the interpretative depth of Joachim’s and Blanshard’s legacy, but also significance of translation for the philosophical enquiry into the nature of truth.
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 27 - 42
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.002.18692Przekład Grzegorz Słowiński
Grzegorz Słowiński
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 43 - 63
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.004.18694"De incerti aestimatione" ("On the estimation of uncertain things") by G.W. Leibniz in 1678 is an attempt to derive a general method for the problem of points, that is, the division of the stake in any round of the game. The explanatory section contains a number of definitions and ideas appearing in Leibniz's writings in earlier years. Among them is a definition of the concept of probability (probabilitas) associated at the time with the still unfinished debate over moral-theological probabilism. This association is justified in this case by the fact that in his correspondence and later writings Leibniz proposes to consider probability in a mathematical sense as opposed to the meaning used in moral theology. "De incerti aestimatione" is Leibniz's second work, in which he devotes attention to games, the issue of their justice and expected value, which he calls hope. The article discusses the legal, moral and metaphysical contexts of the concepts of probabilitas, jus (law) and ratio, as well as the limitations of the moral application of probability. Leibniz's solution to the problem of points is also presented, which, although flawed, is an independent proposal from Pascal for applying the recursive method to this problem.
Robert Grzywacz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 65 - 83
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.003.18693The present study examines the dialectical relationship between the two emblematic factors of human identity distinguished by Paul Ricoeur – character and keeping one’s word. The first part of the text will articulate objections to the philosophical significance of this distinction in the order of justification, as well as suspicions about its non-philosophical genesis and, consequently, regarding its philosophicality in the order of discovery. The second part of the article presents an interpretive proposal for another justification of the dialectic under consideration – a justification inspired by the post-secular thought of Jürgen Habermas, which, moreover, grows out of a different context of discovery, as it engages in the debate on freedom from the standpoint of naturalistic determinism and evolutionary theory. It seems, therefore, that invoking the position of a prominent Frankfurter can provide an interesting counterpoint to the indicated suspicions.
Karol Klimaszyk
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 85 - 113
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.005.18695This text aims to describe and analyse a figure of the third used by Emmanuel Lévinas in the three phases of the evolution of his concept. I interpret the term included in the title on an anthropological ground by analysing the transformations of terms: il y a and illeite, which I define as the third. On a social level, I explore the terms used by the French philosopher: troisieme homme and le tiers, defining them collectively as the third party. The basic thesis argued in the paper is the claim, absent in the Polish-language source literature, that Lévinas is most of all a philosopher of the third. I claim that the figure of the third is the starting point of the formation of subjectivity, defines the evolution of concepts and conditions metaphysics. On the socio-political level, the third defines the positive justification of society, influences the reformulation of the question of responsibility, and through this, in Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, makes it possible to formulate an answer to the doubts related to the unlimited responsibility for the other versus the question of violence in the context of the ethical relation. I also propose a different interpretation from the popular one of the evolution of the concept as a search for a positive justification of social relations.
Przemysław Suchanecki
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 115 - 165
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.006.18696The following article is an exploration of the intellectual journey of the French philosopher Michel Foucault in its latest period, from the Will to Knowledge, first book of the History of Sexuality, up to the later idea of care-of-the-self. The idea of the care-of-the-self is treated here as the culmination of Foucault’s philosophy, as well as its most mature expression. Maturity here means that, according to this concept, the subject is not perceived as the passive outcome of games played between the forces of knowledge and power, as it was presented in the writings of Foucault from the 1960s and 1970s, but, thanks to his own actions, directed at himself, so called practices of the Self, the subject is able to create itself, in separation from the outside influences that bind him. In the context and in contrast to the idea of the care of self is the idea of self-knowledge, a solely intellectual perspective, for which – according to Foucault – the care of the self was abandoned by philosophers for many centuries. A part of the goal of this study is to demonstrate that the concept of the care of the self was introduced through a conceptual evolution, in which certain ideas, gradually changing their meanings, morphed into other ideas, to arrive at the point where the ancient Greek idea of epimeleia heautou, care of the self, was necessary to be introduced. The principal sources for Foucault’s analyses were the writings of Stoics and Epicureans from the 1st and 2nd centuries A.D., as well as the Plato’s dialogue The First Alcibiades. A method of close-reading of the published works of Foucault and the transcripts of his lectures from a period of 1976 to 1982 was used to prove the above mentioned argument. The central goal of this thesis was largely accomplished – it has been demonstrated that Foucault, by examining various Stoic and Epicurean practices of the Self, showed that the subject is not determined to be formed solely as a result of the games of knowledge and power. Thanks to the concept of care of the self, Foucault had drawn a much larger margin of freedom for the individual, than he did in his earlier works.
Wojciech Żak
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 167 - 192
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.007.18697The article points out the elements of Karl Jaspers’ epistemological conception that cross out the possibility of a comprehensive account of being. The key issue here is the limits of cognition, which take the form of object cognition. The theme of limits points to the inadequacies of human thinking in the context of quantifiable and absolutist representations of reality. The impossibility of adequately grasping the totality of reality will be illustrated here by means of the criticism Jaspers levelled at absolutising metaphysics. In connection with the description of the structure of cognition proposed by Jaspers, the article points out the conceptual proximity of the issue of worldview and metaphysics in the light of the thought of the cited author.
Paulina Pikiewicz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 193 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.008.18698Jakub Węgrecki
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 215 - 219
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.009.18699Paweł Rojek, Tropy i uniwersalia. Badania ontologiczne, Wydawnictwo Naukowe Semper, Warszawa 2019.
Giulia Cirillo
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 5 - 26
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.001.18691
It is easy to fall for a conceptual beauty and simplicity of the coherence theory of truth. But the texts in which its foundations were for the first time explicitly developed are rich in subtleties, defying a consistent interpretation and inviting various forms of criticism. That is why the following study will take one more look at the writings of Harold H. Joachim and Brand Blanshard, in order to prove that in the analyses which they proposed there is an additional, so far unrecognised element – namely the process of translation – which plays a crucial role in making their accounts valid and complete. Initially then, the article will specify how the notion of translation should be here understood. Next, key postulates of both theories will be recalled, with an indication of several potential inconsistencies which they might entail. Finally, the analysis exposes translative ground of each reconstructed model.
What will be thereby underscored, is not only the interpretative depth of Joachim’s and Blanshard’s legacy, but also significance of translation for the philosophical enquiry into the nature of truth.
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 27 - 42
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.002.18692Przekład Grzegorz Słowiński
Grzegorz Słowiński
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 43 - 63
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.004.18694"De incerti aestimatione" ("On the estimation of uncertain things") by G.W. Leibniz in 1678 is an attempt to derive a general method for the problem of points, that is, the division of the stake in any round of the game. The explanatory section contains a number of definitions and ideas appearing in Leibniz's writings in earlier years. Among them is a definition of the concept of probability (probabilitas) associated at the time with the still unfinished debate over moral-theological probabilism. This association is justified in this case by the fact that in his correspondence and later writings Leibniz proposes to consider probability in a mathematical sense as opposed to the meaning used in moral theology. "De incerti aestimatione" is Leibniz's second work, in which he devotes attention to games, the issue of their justice and expected value, which he calls hope. The article discusses the legal, moral and metaphysical contexts of the concepts of probabilitas, jus (law) and ratio, as well as the limitations of the moral application of probability. Leibniz's solution to the problem of points is also presented, which, although flawed, is an independent proposal from Pascal for applying the recursive method to this problem.
Robert Grzywacz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 65 - 83
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.003.18693The present study examines the dialectical relationship between the two emblematic factors of human identity distinguished by Paul Ricoeur – character and keeping one’s word. The first part of the text will articulate objections to the philosophical significance of this distinction in the order of justification, as well as suspicions about its non-philosophical genesis and, consequently, regarding its philosophicality in the order of discovery. The second part of the article presents an interpretive proposal for another justification of the dialectic under consideration – a justification inspired by the post-secular thought of Jürgen Habermas, which, moreover, grows out of a different context of discovery, as it engages in the debate on freedom from the standpoint of naturalistic determinism and evolutionary theory. It seems, therefore, that invoking the position of a prominent Frankfurter can provide an interesting counterpoint to the indicated suspicions.
Karol Klimaszyk
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 85 - 113
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.005.18695This text aims to describe and analyse a figure of the third used by Emmanuel Lévinas in the three phases of the evolution of his concept. I interpret the term included in the title on an anthropological ground by analysing the transformations of terms: il y a and illeite, which I define as the third. On a social level, I explore the terms used by the French philosopher: troisieme homme and le tiers, defining them collectively as the third party. The basic thesis argued in the paper is the claim, absent in the Polish-language source literature, that Lévinas is most of all a philosopher of the third. I claim that the figure of the third is the starting point of the formation of subjectivity, defines the evolution of concepts and conditions metaphysics. On the socio-political level, the third defines the positive justification of society, influences the reformulation of the question of responsibility, and through this, in Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, makes it possible to formulate an answer to the doubts related to the unlimited responsibility for the other versus the question of violence in the context of the ethical relation. I also propose a different interpretation from the popular one of the evolution of the concept as a search for a positive justification of social relations.
Przemysław Suchanecki
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 115 - 165
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.006.18696The following article is an exploration of the intellectual journey of the French philosopher Michel Foucault in its latest period, from the Will to Knowledge, first book of the History of Sexuality, up to the later idea of care-of-the-self. The idea of the care-of-the-self is treated here as the culmination of Foucault’s philosophy, as well as its most mature expression. Maturity here means that, according to this concept, the subject is not perceived as the passive outcome of games played between the forces of knowledge and power, as it was presented in the writings of Foucault from the 1960s and 1970s, but, thanks to his own actions, directed at himself, so called practices of the Self, the subject is able to create itself, in separation from the outside influences that bind him. In the context and in contrast to the idea of the care of self is the idea of self-knowledge, a solely intellectual perspective, for which – according to Foucault – the care of the self was abandoned by philosophers for many centuries. A part of the goal of this study is to demonstrate that the concept of the care of the self was introduced through a conceptual evolution, in which certain ideas, gradually changing their meanings, morphed into other ideas, to arrive at the point where the ancient Greek idea of epimeleia heautou, care of the self, was necessary to be introduced. The principal sources for Foucault’s analyses were the writings of Stoics and Epicureans from the 1st and 2nd centuries A.D., as well as the Plato’s dialogue The First Alcibiades. A method of close-reading of the published works of Foucault and the transcripts of his lectures from a period of 1976 to 1982 was used to prove the above mentioned argument. The central goal of this thesis was largely accomplished – it has been demonstrated that Foucault, by examining various Stoic and Epicurean practices of the Self, showed that the subject is not determined to be formed solely as a result of the games of knowledge and power. Thanks to the concept of care of the self, Foucault had drawn a much larger margin of freedom for the individual, than he did in his earlier works.
Wojciech Żak
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 167 - 192
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.007.18697The article points out the elements of Karl Jaspers’ epistemological conception that cross out the possibility of a comprehensive account of being. The key issue here is the limits of cognition, which take the form of object cognition. The theme of limits points to the inadequacies of human thinking in the context of quantifiable and absolutist representations of reality. The impossibility of adequately grasping the totality of reality will be illustrated here by means of the criticism Jaspers levelled at absolutising metaphysics. In connection with the description of the structure of cognition proposed by Jaspers, the article points out the conceptual proximity of the issue of worldview and metaphysics in the light of the thought of the cited author.
Paulina Pikiewicz
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 193 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.008.18698Jakub Węgrecki
Principia, Volume 68, 2021, pp. 215 - 219
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.21.009.18699Paweł Rojek, Tropy i uniwersalia. Badania ontologiczne, Wydawnictwo Naukowe Semper, Warszawa 2019.
Publication date: 21.12.2020
Editor-in-Chief: Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Marek Maciejczak
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 5 - 25
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.001.13831Consciousness, according to one of Husserl’s characteristics, is also a system of potential moments outlined in advance. How does consciousness gain this competence? Answering the question, subsequent conditioning aspects are taken into account: (1.) the inner time consciousness that determinates the temporal structure of the word-experience (Welterfahrung) and the world consciousness (Weltbewusstsein), (2.) the network of types. The two aspects of consciousness make possible and determinate cognitive styles of present and future course of experience. The closing remarks (3.) concern the nature of types and their role as cognitive structures that integrate common knowledge with scientific knowledge. Types combined into wider structures types define the further course of experience. Ultimately, they define the scope of practical possibilities, purposes and interests of the subject, an open horizon of possible closer specification.
Dorota Rybarkiewicz
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 27 - 47
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.002.13832Some changes in the environment, when attended to, result in cognitive response which may be called thinking with change. Thinking with change is similar to the “algorithm of sense detection” of metaphors. In fact, the interpretation of any kind of metaphor is framed by the general human mechanism of dealing with a change. Therefore an interpreted (meaningful) change is here called metaphorical. The first part clarifies the concepts of change and metaphor. The second part provides the characteristics of metaphorical changes. Finally, we try to answer the question if metaphorical thinking with change is rational.
Grzegorz Francuz
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 49 - 85
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.003.13833Questions about the intrinsic value of nature are not only an abstract philosophical speculation, they have a practical meaning, can inspire and motivate people to act. Environmental ethics attempts to overcome the anthropocentric and personalistic attitude of traditional ethics. It emphasizes the intrinsic value of nature, value, which is independent from humans.
Within non-anthropocentric environmental ethics there are individualistic and holistic trends. Biocentric individualism raises problems with resolving conflicts of interests of different organisms, with the hierarchy of beings, while holistic ethics does not count with the well-being of individuals. Ethical holism should be contrasted with practical holism as a methodological postulate.
The pragmatic current of ecological ethics acknowledges that the good of people and the intrinsic good of nature coincide. In a pluralistic, liberal society there should be a convergence of radical, biocentric and moderate, anthropocentric concepts of ecological ethics.
Jerzy Pogonowski
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 87 - 118
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.004.13834Certain mathematical objects are called paradoxical or pathological. Such terms have negative connotations in common usage, in psychology, and in social science. However, the situation is different in mathematics. Emergence of mathematical paradoxes or pathologies always indicates a creative moment in the process of mathematical discovery. The paper contains reflections on this creative aspect of mathematical pathologies, the process of their domestication, and the cognitive accessibility of mathematical objects. The work on this paper was sponsored by the National Scientific Center research grant 2015/17/B/HS1/02232 Extremal axioms: logical, mathematical and cognitive aspects. The paper was presented during the 11th Polish Philosophical Congress in Lublin (2019).
Anna Pietryga
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 119 - 131
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.005.13835Traditional syllogistics sugests inferring a result about the binary relation between sets from the two categorical premisses each of which state something about a relation between one of them to a third set (whose name is called the middle term).
Since the Middle Ages it is known how to check the formal correctness of a syllogism by the detailed analysis of its syntax, and since the 19th century also how to present the premisses graphically on the Venn diagram for three sets, whose mutual binary relations consttute the subject of syllogistics. The non-empty sum of subregions is sometimes not very comfortable to deal with.
In the paper a new method is described for presenting syllogisms premisses, which consists in indicating the subregions, in which the premisses say some elements may or have to be located and those subregions which are announced empty. In particular, for the non-empty sum of two regions the rhotal relation is suggested together with the the possible corresponding empty region, had it been suitably indicated by one ot he premisses.
Mariusz Oziębłowski
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 133 - 157
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.006.13836Basing on the concept by Richard Rorty and Hans George Gadamer a hermeneutic idea of aesthetic integration and self-creation is analysed and their significance for paradigmatic transformation, which results in postmodern society, is discussed. The relation between cognitive and integrating function of experiencing the art is presented. Relations between experiencing historical catastrophes and the opportunity of paradigmatic transformation are discussed with the use of the argumentation of Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz. The reasons why aesthetic integration cannot become the tool to stop the catastrophe are presented.
Włodzimierz Lorenc
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 159 - 182
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.007.13837Radical hope is hope that could be found in religious discourse. Starting from Nietzsche, the concept entered also philosophical discourse. The article takes as its starting point the thought of Ernest Bloch, who placed hope at the center of philosophical thought, although, he was not able to develop the idea. In this respect, priority should be given to Nietzsche, whose views were taken up by Quentin Meillasoux, who has been aiming to philosophically uphold hope that has been usually associated with religion. The end point of the present deliberation, in addition to an attempt at evaluating the abovementioned philosophers’ propositions, is formulation conclusions concerning the consequences of the appearance of the problematics of radical hope in the field of philosophy. I will point to a way of contemporary practice of philosophy, which appears to open up opportunities to tie in this problematics with philosophy.
Andrzej Sołtys
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 183 - 207
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.009.13839In the context of the multiplicity of concepts of the person and their importance for the way in which man organizes his individual and social life, a turn toward a realistic concept of the person is crucial. In this study, a critical analysis of several selected relational concepts of the person from the position of existential Thomism is carried out. As a result of the analysis, the assumed hypothesis was confirmed that the selected relational conceptions of the person are a priori, however, only with regard to the essence of the person. The study answers the question of why the analysed concepts do not explain the very essence of the real human person, but only point to its identifying features, describing the existence and ways of fulfilment of person.
Joanna Skurzak
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 209 - 232
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.010.13840The purpose of the article is the analysis of a specific understanding of contemporary atheism, which 1) arose in the French philosophical circles in the 20th and 21st century; 2) combines a critique of religion (more or less radical) with a positive proposal of replacing traditional religious spirituality with an atheist spirituality. The goal of this research is to verify the following hypotheses: 1) a “new spirituality” is an proposal alternative to traditional “religious spiritualities”, addressing atheits; 2) this new “secular spirituality” is in many aspects similar to religious spirituality, with its difference being the new ways of understanding immortality and the ways of overcoming the fear of death; 3) “atheist spirituality”, as a support for the criticque of religious positions, may encourage traditionally religious people to accept a spirituality that requires no relation to personalized Transcendence.Research will be conducted on the base of a critical analysis of the sources of four French thinkers: M. Onfray, L. Ferry, M. Gauchet and A. Comte-Sponville.
Dorota Sepczyńska
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 233 - 267
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.011.13841These two papers contribute to the research tendency that seeks an analogy between the ethics of care and other ethical theories. The purpose of this study is to compare the ethics of care with Edward Abramowski’s moral theory. The critical appraisal of both theories requires the reconstruction and confrontation of issues such as friendship‑brotherhood‑care, response to the needs of others, and making friendship‑brotherhood‑care public. The analysis of philosophical sources was carried out with the use of tools from hermeneutics and the history of ideas. In the case of the ethics of care, both the theories of direct caring relations and of group, institutional caring relations were examined. The analysis of Abramowski’s philosophy is focused on the ethics of friendship. In Part I, the ethics of care and the ethics of friendship are presented. Part II refers the results obtained from the analysis of the ethics of friendship to the theses and arguments which feature in the ethics of care.
Marek Maciejczak
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 5 - 25
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.001.13831Consciousness, according to one of Husserl’s characteristics, is also a system of potential moments outlined in advance. How does consciousness gain this competence? Answering the question, subsequent conditioning aspects are taken into account: (1.) the inner time consciousness that determinates the temporal structure of the word-experience (Welterfahrung) and the world consciousness (Weltbewusstsein), (2.) the network of types. The two aspects of consciousness make possible and determinate cognitive styles of present and future course of experience. The closing remarks (3.) concern the nature of types and their role as cognitive structures that integrate common knowledge with scientific knowledge. Types combined into wider structures types define the further course of experience. Ultimately, they define the scope of practical possibilities, purposes and interests of the subject, an open horizon of possible closer specification.
Dorota Rybarkiewicz
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 27 - 47
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.002.13832Some changes in the environment, when attended to, result in cognitive response which may be called thinking with change. Thinking with change is similar to the “algorithm of sense detection” of metaphors. In fact, the interpretation of any kind of metaphor is framed by the general human mechanism of dealing with a change. Therefore an interpreted (meaningful) change is here called metaphorical. The first part clarifies the concepts of change and metaphor. The second part provides the characteristics of metaphorical changes. Finally, we try to answer the question if metaphorical thinking with change is rational.
Grzegorz Francuz
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 49 - 85
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.003.13833Questions about the intrinsic value of nature are not only an abstract philosophical speculation, they have a practical meaning, can inspire and motivate people to act. Environmental ethics attempts to overcome the anthropocentric and personalistic attitude of traditional ethics. It emphasizes the intrinsic value of nature, value, which is independent from humans.
Within non-anthropocentric environmental ethics there are individualistic and holistic trends. Biocentric individualism raises problems with resolving conflicts of interests of different organisms, with the hierarchy of beings, while holistic ethics does not count with the well-being of individuals. Ethical holism should be contrasted with practical holism as a methodological postulate.
The pragmatic current of ecological ethics acknowledges that the good of people and the intrinsic good of nature coincide. In a pluralistic, liberal society there should be a convergence of radical, biocentric and moderate, anthropocentric concepts of ecological ethics.
Jerzy Pogonowski
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 87 - 118
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.004.13834Certain mathematical objects are called paradoxical or pathological. Such terms have negative connotations in common usage, in psychology, and in social science. However, the situation is different in mathematics. Emergence of mathematical paradoxes or pathologies always indicates a creative moment in the process of mathematical discovery. The paper contains reflections on this creative aspect of mathematical pathologies, the process of their domestication, and the cognitive accessibility of mathematical objects. The work on this paper was sponsored by the National Scientific Center research grant 2015/17/B/HS1/02232 Extremal axioms: logical, mathematical and cognitive aspects. The paper was presented during the 11th Polish Philosophical Congress in Lublin (2019).
Anna Pietryga
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 119 - 131
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.005.13835Traditional syllogistics sugests inferring a result about the binary relation between sets from the two categorical premisses each of which state something about a relation between one of them to a third set (whose name is called the middle term).
Since the Middle Ages it is known how to check the formal correctness of a syllogism by the detailed analysis of its syntax, and since the 19th century also how to present the premisses graphically on the Venn diagram for three sets, whose mutual binary relations consttute the subject of syllogistics. The non-empty sum of subregions is sometimes not very comfortable to deal with.
In the paper a new method is described for presenting syllogisms premisses, which consists in indicating the subregions, in which the premisses say some elements may or have to be located and those subregions which are announced empty. In particular, for the non-empty sum of two regions the rhotal relation is suggested together with the the possible corresponding empty region, had it been suitably indicated by one ot he premisses.
Mariusz Oziębłowski
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 133 - 157
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.006.13836Basing on the concept by Richard Rorty and Hans George Gadamer a hermeneutic idea of aesthetic integration and self-creation is analysed and their significance for paradigmatic transformation, which results in postmodern society, is discussed. The relation between cognitive and integrating function of experiencing the art is presented. Relations between experiencing historical catastrophes and the opportunity of paradigmatic transformation are discussed with the use of the argumentation of Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz. The reasons why aesthetic integration cannot become the tool to stop the catastrophe are presented.
Włodzimierz Lorenc
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 159 - 182
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.007.13837Radical hope is hope that could be found in religious discourse. Starting from Nietzsche, the concept entered also philosophical discourse. The article takes as its starting point the thought of Ernest Bloch, who placed hope at the center of philosophical thought, although, he was not able to develop the idea. In this respect, priority should be given to Nietzsche, whose views were taken up by Quentin Meillasoux, who has been aiming to philosophically uphold hope that has been usually associated with religion. The end point of the present deliberation, in addition to an attempt at evaluating the abovementioned philosophers’ propositions, is formulation conclusions concerning the consequences of the appearance of the problematics of radical hope in the field of philosophy. I will point to a way of contemporary practice of philosophy, which appears to open up opportunities to tie in this problematics with philosophy.
Andrzej Sołtys
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 183 - 207
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.009.13839In the context of the multiplicity of concepts of the person and their importance for the way in which man organizes his individual and social life, a turn toward a realistic concept of the person is crucial. In this study, a critical analysis of several selected relational concepts of the person from the position of existential Thomism is carried out. As a result of the analysis, the assumed hypothesis was confirmed that the selected relational conceptions of the person are a priori, however, only with regard to the essence of the person. The study answers the question of why the analysed concepts do not explain the very essence of the real human person, but only point to its identifying features, describing the existence and ways of fulfilment of person.
Joanna Skurzak
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 209 - 232
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.010.13840The purpose of the article is the analysis of a specific understanding of contemporary atheism, which 1) arose in the French philosophical circles in the 20th and 21st century; 2) combines a critique of religion (more or less radical) with a positive proposal of replacing traditional religious spirituality with an atheist spirituality. The goal of this research is to verify the following hypotheses: 1) a “new spirituality” is an proposal alternative to traditional “religious spiritualities”, addressing atheits; 2) this new “secular spirituality” is in many aspects similar to religious spirituality, with its difference being the new ways of understanding immortality and the ways of overcoming the fear of death; 3) “atheist spirituality”, as a support for the criticque of religious positions, may encourage traditionally religious people to accept a spirituality that requires no relation to personalized Transcendence.Research will be conducted on the base of a critical analysis of the sources of four French thinkers: M. Onfray, L. Ferry, M. Gauchet and A. Comte-Sponville.
Dorota Sepczyńska
Principia, Volume 67, 2020, pp. 233 - 267
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.20.011.13841These two papers contribute to the research tendency that seeks an analogy between the ethics of care and other ethical theories. The purpose of this study is to compare the ethics of care with Edward Abramowski’s moral theory. The critical appraisal of both theories requires the reconstruction and confrontation of issues such as friendship‑brotherhood‑care, response to the needs of others, and making friendship‑brotherhood‑care public. The analysis of philosophical sources was carried out with the use of tools from hermeneutics and the history of ideas. In the case of the ethics of care, both the theories of direct caring relations and of group, institutional caring relations were examined. The analysis of Abramowski’s philosophy is focused on the ethics of friendship. In Part I, the ethics of care and the ethics of friendship are presented. Part II refers the results obtained from the analysis of the ethics of friendship to the theses and arguments which feature in the ethics of care.
Publication date: 20.12.2019
Editor-in-Chief: Krzysztof Guczalski
Volume Editor: Marcin Waligóra
Susana Cadilha
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 5 - 33
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.001.11634In this paper I will analyze John McDowell’s broad account of practical rationality and moral reasons, which he mainly puts forward in his articles “Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives?” (1978) and “Might there be external reasons?” (1995). My main aim is to argue that from a philosophical perspective, no less than from an empirical one, McDowell’s account of practical rationality is not a realistic one. From a philosophical point of view, I will argue that his intellectualist account is not convincing; and if we consider his virtue-ethical ideal of practical rationality in light of the model of human cognition, we also realize that moral behavior is not immune to cognitive biases and does not always flow from robust traits of character like virtues. At the same time, this puts at stake his strong thesis of moral autonomy – the idea that with the ‘onset of reason’ moral beings are no longer determined by ‘first nature’ features.
Gabriel Bednarz
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 35 - 58
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.002.11635Brian Leiter
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 59 - 85
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.003.11636The majority of legal systems in Western democracies accord special treatment to religions, e.g. exemptions from generally applicable laws if they conflict with religious convictions. Other beliefs do not usually enjoy such far‑reaching tolerance on the part of the state. The article raises the question of how granting such privilege to religious views can be justified. Arguments of some philosophers (e.g. Thomas Hobbes’) which suggest that an intolerant attitude might sometimes be disadvantageous are in fact only instrumental, and do not prove that tolerance is a moral virtue. This last claim only follows from the arguments of John Stuart Mill and John Rawls, who exemplify two basic approaches in ethics, i.e. utilitarianism and deontology. None of the analyzed arguments for freedom of conscience and religion distinguishes between religious and other beliefs, which suggests that the existing differences in their moral and legal treatment cannot be justified. Therefore, the question arises of whether legal regulations regarding religious and other beliefs should not be equated, so that religious views are not privileged.
Dorota Sepczyńska
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 86 - 125
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.004.11637Krzysztof Moraczewski
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 127 - 163
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.005.11638The general aim of the essay is to pose the question of the relationship between the elements of a socially shared, general image of the world (using Aron Gurevich’s terminology) and the possibility of constructing the idea of autonomous music. Musical autonomy is understood here as the thesis that the order of music is independent from any other order, e.g. social, cultural etc. Hence the focus of these considerations is on cultural images of music that situate music beyond external social conditions. Several possibilities of this type are considered, such as the Pythagorean connection between music and the cosmic order, the Iranian concept of Aša, and the ancient Chinese connection between music and the cosmo-political order. Shamanism is considered as a possible archaic source for this kind of mental operation. These considerations do not aim at any kind of archaistic reduction, but rather at describing the cultural-historical conditions that made the very idea of autonomous music possible.
Marcin Trzęsiok
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 163 - 185
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.006.11639Music occupies a special place in George Steiner’s thinking: “Three areas: the essence and name of God, higher mathematics and music (what is the connection between them?) are located at the limits of language” (Steiner, Errata). The seemingly rhetorical question in parentheses turns out to be a source of deep controversy, the essence of which is revealed in historical-genealogical reflection. Steiner attempts to incorporate Romantic metaphysics within the traditional scholastic symbiosis of Biblical creationism and Pythagoreanism, which reveals his philosophy of music to be entangled in a range of contradictions. On the one hand, a critical reading of Steiner's works uncovers the difficulties posed by the attempt to reconcile pre- and post-Enlightenment culture; on the other hand, the still unused opportunities offered by Romanticism and its modernist continuations are clearly visible. Musical aesthetics, rooted in the idea of infinity, plays a crucial role in these divagations.
Krzysztof Szwajgier
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 187 - 208
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.007.11640The arche–arte dualism (concrete–abstract) is fundamental and basic, due to its universality and comprehensive generative function. This duality characterizes our actions in every dimension, and is thus necessarily involved in cognitive and creative acts. The “arteic” includes the categories of consciousness, consideration, calculation, ordering, knowledge, intellect, and artificiality. On the other hand, the “archeic” refers to that which is, in us, subconscious, eternal, primordial, innate, instinctive, and natural. When this basic duality is posited at the outset, it furnishes an analytical‑interpretative‑synthesizing tool that can be applied to diverse facts. The omnipresence and explanatory potential of the arche‑arte dualism are illustrated through musical examples. The dual nature of sound is thereby revealed to be a structural model for the subconscious sensations that music evokes in us.
Krzysztof Moraczewski
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 127 - 163
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.005.11638The general aim of the essay is to pose the question of the relationship between the elements of a socially shared, general image of the world (using Aron Gurevich’s terminology) and the possibility of constructing the idea of autonomous music. Musical autonomy is understood here as the thesis that the order of music is independent from any other order, e.g. social, cultural etc. Hence the focus of these considerations is on cultural images of music that situate music beyond external social conditions. Several possibilities of this type are considered, such as the Pythagorean connection between music and the cosmic order, the Iranian concept of Aša, and the ancient Chinese connection between music and the cosmo-political order. Shamanism is considered as a possible archaic source for this kind of mental operation. These considerations do not aim at any kind of archaistic reduction, but rather at describing the cultural-historical conditions that made the very idea of autonomous music possible.
Marcin Trzęsiok
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 163 - 185
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.006.11639Music occupies a special place in George Steiner’s thinking: “Three areas: the essence and name of God, higher mathematics and music (what is the connection between them?) are located at the limits of language” (Steiner, Errata). The seemingly rhetorical question in parentheses turns out to be a source of deep controversy, the essence of which is revealed in historical-genealogical reflection. Steiner attempts to incorporate Romantic metaphysics within the traditional scholastic symbiosis of Biblical creationism and Pythagoreanism, which reveals his philosophy of music to be entangled in a range of contradictions. On the one hand, a critical reading of Steiner's works uncovers the difficulties posed by the attempt to reconcile pre- and post-Enlightenment culture; on the other hand, the still unused opportunities offered by Romanticism and its modernist continuations are clearly visible. Musical aesthetics, rooted in the idea of infinity, plays a crucial role in these divagations.
Krzysztof Szwajgier
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 187 - 208
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.007.11640The arche–arte dualism (concrete–abstract) is fundamental and basic, due to its universality and comprehensive generative function. This duality characterizes our actions in every dimension, and is thus necessarily involved in cognitive and creative acts. The “arteic” includes the categories of consciousness, consideration, calculation, ordering, knowledge, intellect, and artificiality. On the other hand, the “archeic” refers to that which is, in us, subconscious, eternal, primordial, innate, instinctive, and natural. When this basic duality is posited at the outset, it furnishes an analytical‑interpretative‑synthesizing tool that can be applied to diverse facts. The omnipresence and explanatory potential of the arche‑arte dualism are illustrated through musical examples. The dual nature of sound is thereby revealed to be a structural model for the subconscious sensations that music evokes in us.
Susana Cadilha
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 5 - 33
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.001.11634In this paper I will analyze John McDowell’s broad account of practical rationality and moral reasons, which he mainly puts forward in his articles “Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives?” (1978) and “Might there be external reasons?” (1995). My main aim is to argue that from a philosophical perspective, no less than from an empirical one, McDowell’s account of practical rationality is not a realistic one. From a philosophical point of view, I will argue that his intellectualist account is not convincing; and if we consider his virtue-ethical ideal of practical rationality in light of the model of human cognition, we also realize that moral behavior is not immune to cognitive biases and does not always flow from robust traits of character like virtues. At the same time, this puts at stake his strong thesis of moral autonomy – the idea that with the ‘onset of reason’ moral beings are no longer determined by ‘first nature’ features.
Gabriel Bednarz
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 35 - 58
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.002.11635Brian Leiter
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 59 - 85
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.003.11636The majority of legal systems in Western democracies accord special treatment to religions, e.g. exemptions from generally applicable laws if they conflict with religious convictions. Other beliefs do not usually enjoy such far‑reaching tolerance on the part of the state. The article raises the question of how granting such privilege to religious views can be justified. Arguments of some philosophers (e.g. Thomas Hobbes’) which suggest that an intolerant attitude might sometimes be disadvantageous are in fact only instrumental, and do not prove that tolerance is a moral virtue. This last claim only follows from the arguments of John Stuart Mill and John Rawls, who exemplify two basic approaches in ethics, i.e. utilitarianism and deontology. None of the analyzed arguments for freedom of conscience and religion distinguishes between religious and other beliefs, which suggests that the existing differences in their moral and legal treatment cannot be justified. Therefore, the question arises of whether legal regulations regarding religious and other beliefs should not be equated, so that religious views are not privileged.
Dorota Sepczyńska
Principia, Volume 66, 2019, pp. 86 - 125
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.19.004.11637Publication date: 2018
Editor-in-Chief: Krzysztof Guczalski
Volume Editors: Tomasz Bekrycht, Krzysztof Guczalski
Florian Ederer, Alexander Stremitzer
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 5 - 33
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.010.10869Promises are a pervasive and important feature of real-world economic exchange situations. We investigate lay people’s intuitions of promise keeping. We study the effect of mutual promises, the dynamic of promising and performance over time, the effect of continuous as opposed to binary performance decisions, the effect of income, and the role the receipt of a promise plays on promise-keeping. Assuming that law serves as a backstop of moral intuitions, our results cast some light on the mutuality requirement, the doctrine of substantial performance, doctrines of divisible obligations, and doctrines of contract formation.
JEL-Classification: K12, A13, C91, C72
Jakub J. Szczerbowski
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 35 - 47
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.001.9884The goal of this text is to pose hypotheses related to use of heuristics in the process of deciding cases related to pure economic loss and making laws governing liability for it. Pure economic losses are a type of injury where the victim only suffers economically, i.e. there is no bodily harm or injury to property, and there is a lack of a contractual nexus between the victim and the tortfeasor. Pure economic losses are, in principle, not recoverable in common law systems and, in principle, recoverable in civil law systems. Pure economic losses are a heterogenic category consisting of a variety of case types, here divided into (1) ricochet loss, (2) transferred loss, (3) loss induced by faulty information. Cases of pure economic loss are usually more complex, compared to physical injuries and consequential economic losses, as they may involve a loss of profits. This paper explores the use of heuristics in the process of deciding pure economic loss cases and in the process of forming general norms related to them.
Wojciech Załuski
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 49 - 68
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.002.9885Psychologists have noticed an interesting regularity consisting in the fact that people are more willing to help so-called identified victims than so-called statistical victims (this regularity has been called ‘the identifiable victim effect’). One of the controversial problems connected with this effect is a normative one, viz. can preferring identified victims be morally justified in the contexts of private decisions (i.e., made by ‘private’ citizens rather than public institutions)? The goal of this article is to defend three claims: (1) that the answer to the above normative question depends on two factors: the strength of the identified victims effect and the assumed view (utilitarian or non-utilitarian) on the normative status of helping; (2) that the proper view is one of the variants of the non-utilitarian approach (called in the paper ‘negative morality’ with elements of positive-partial morality); (3) that (with the exception of the strong variant of the identified victim effect) preferring identified victims is not morally improper.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Michał Kłusek
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 69 - 89
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.003.9886The identified victim effect refers to a psychological bias of a much greater willingness to help identified victims, as opposed to statistical ones. The aim of this article is to assess what we morally ought to do in the light of this effect, from the point of view of utilitarian ethics. What decision-making rule ought to be established? Ought we to always help identified victims or statistical ones? I argue for a rule that constitutes a middle ground between the two extremes. Next, using the example of the Polish non-governmental sector and with the rule in mind, I outline legal changes that would result in a much higher overall net utility. The first change concerns the rules of the so-called percentage tax designation mechanism. The second concerns the conditions NGOs have to meet in order to receive public funding of their activities.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Szymon Osmola
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 91 - 111
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.004.9887Is it possible to make a binding promise to an unidentified individual, i.e. an individual whose identity is unknown to a promisor? The answer to this question seems to be negative, regardless of the philosophical theory of promises one decides to adopt. Particular autonomy theories consider promises to be one of the tools for enhancing morally valuable relationships through recognizing another party's particular personality, which enables individuals to live a better life. The generic autonomy theories consider promises to be a tool facilitating cooperation between strangers. The utilitarian theories consider the practice of promising to be a tool for increasing social welfare. The premises of each of these theories seem to rule out the possibility of promises to unidentified individuals. Accordingly, reflections on this topic may some shed light on some problems related to the issue of the identifiability effect, which is widely discussed in the psychological literature.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Adam Michał Dyrda
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 113 - 143
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.005.9888Analyses of the concept of law rely on certain self-evident truths: truisms (platitudes) about law that people generally share and which reflect their common understanding of this important social concept. General legal theories are products of such analyses. In this paper I argue that every reference to truisms in the context of legal theory building should also take into account inferential processes by which truisms themselves are coined, namely different types of heuristics about law and related phenomena. Since both truisms and heuristics are unstructured, often inconsistent, and even fallible, conceptual analyses are the main means of transforming such “raw” evidence into rationally structured legal theories.
This paper was written as a result of research project no. 2016/21/D/HS5/03839, financed by the Polish National Science Centre.
Przemysław Kaczmarek
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 145 - 165
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.006.9889Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 167 - 184
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.007.9890The problems associated with understanding law as the regulator of social relations involve many separate issues which undoubtedly constitute intellectual challenges for the philosophy of law. In this context, the philosophy of law inquires, inter alia, about whether law exists as a universal structure of the category of being, and about the possibility of the objective cognition of law as an ontological and deontological category. However, it transpires that this task is by no means easy, when it comes to questions concerning epistemological and ontological issues in relation to law – and consequently its justification (the metaphysics of law), and then its legitimation – unequivocal answers are not forthcoming.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/19/B/HS5/03114
Monika Zalewska
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 185 - 206
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.008.9891The article examines the cognitive, metaphorical dimension of the pure theory of law and demonstrates that Hans Kelsen used metaphorical language in his description of law, and unintentionally created a unique set of cognitive metaphors in order to make a theory of law focused on the abstract “Ought” world comprehensible. The paper argues that it would be impossible for Kelsen to describe norms without metaphors. The paper uses Lakoff and Johnson’s theory as a framework for the interpretation of this metaphorical aspect of the pure theory of law. Hence the following paragraphs will examine the cognitive context of the abstract categories crucial for the pure theory of law, such as: the category of Ought, imputation, basic norms and the dynamic (hierarchical) structure of law. This article is based on the position that an analysis of the cognitive dimension of the pure theory of law might yield promising results which could reveal new aspects of the central categories in this theory. This article is an attempt to explore the possibilities provided by merging these two theories and checking if the result brings some new knowledge about the pure theory of law and legal thinking in general.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/17/B/HS5/00495
Mariusz Jerzy Golecki
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 207 - 231
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.009.10868In his theory of adjudication, Aristotle observes that the judicial process should be based on rational and impartial evaluation of the merits of given case and on the application of law. This paper focuses on the bipolar character of the theory of adjudication analyzed from the perspective of the modern dual process theory. It seems that the bounded rationality of judges may create a potential threat to the impartiality and rationality of judgments in complex cases. In this context the hybrid model of categorization adopted from cognitive psychology is to be confronted with the Aristotelian theory of adjudication. The influence of heuristics and biases on judicial decisions is also to be considered. The conclusion refers to the prospects of an Aristotelian virtue-centered model of adjudication following the assumption of bounded rationality.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/17/B/HS5/00495
Florian Ederer, Alexander Stremitzer
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 5 - 33
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.010.10869Promises are a pervasive and important feature of real-world economic exchange situations. We investigate lay people’s intuitions of promise keeping. We study the effect of mutual promises, the dynamic of promising and performance over time, the effect of continuous as opposed to binary performance decisions, the effect of income, and the role the receipt of a promise plays on promise-keeping. Assuming that law serves as a backstop of moral intuitions, our results cast some light on the mutuality requirement, the doctrine of substantial performance, doctrines of divisible obligations, and doctrines of contract formation.
JEL-Classification: K12, A13, C91, C72
Jakub J. Szczerbowski
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 35 - 47
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.001.9884The goal of this text is to pose hypotheses related to use of heuristics in the process of deciding cases related to pure economic loss and making laws governing liability for it. Pure economic losses are a type of injury where the victim only suffers economically, i.e. there is no bodily harm or injury to property, and there is a lack of a contractual nexus between the victim and the tortfeasor. Pure economic losses are, in principle, not recoverable in common law systems and, in principle, recoverable in civil law systems. Pure economic losses are a heterogenic category consisting of a variety of case types, here divided into (1) ricochet loss, (2) transferred loss, (3) loss induced by faulty information. Cases of pure economic loss are usually more complex, compared to physical injuries and consequential economic losses, as they may involve a loss of profits. This paper explores the use of heuristics in the process of deciding pure economic loss cases and in the process of forming general norms related to them.
Wojciech Załuski
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 49 - 68
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.002.9885Psychologists have noticed an interesting regularity consisting in the fact that people are more willing to help so-called identified victims than so-called statistical victims (this regularity has been called ‘the identifiable victim effect’). One of the controversial problems connected with this effect is a normative one, viz. can preferring identified victims be morally justified in the contexts of private decisions (i.e., made by ‘private’ citizens rather than public institutions)? The goal of this article is to defend three claims: (1) that the answer to the above normative question depends on two factors: the strength of the identified victims effect and the assumed view (utilitarian or non-utilitarian) on the normative status of helping; (2) that the proper view is one of the variants of the non-utilitarian approach (called in the paper ‘negative morality’ with elements of positive-partial morality); (3) that (with the exception of the strong variant of the identified victim effect) preferring identified victims is not morally improper.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Michał Kłusek
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 69 - 89
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.003.9886The identified victim effect refers to a psychological bias of a much greater willingness to help identified victims, as opposed to statistical ones. The aim of this article is to assess what we morally ought to do in the light of this effect, from the point of view of utilitarian ethics. What decision-making rule ought to be established? Ought we to always help identified victims or statistical ones? I argue for a rule that constitutes a middle ground between the two extremes. Next, using the example of the Polish non-governmental sector and with the rule in mind, I outline legal changes that would result in a much higher overall net utility. The first change concerns the rules of the so-called percentage tax designation mechanism. The second concerns the conditions NGOs have to meet in order to receive public funding of their activities.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Szymon Osmola
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 91 - 111
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.004.9887Is it possible to make a binding promise to an unidentified individual, i.e. an individual whose identity is unknown to a promisor? The answer to this question seems to be negative, regardless of the philosophical theory of promises one decides to adopt. Particular autonomy theories consider promises to be one of the tools for enhancing morally valuable relationships through recognizing another party's particular personality, which enables individuals to live a better life. The generic autonomy theories consider promises to be a tool facilitating cooperation between strangers. The utilitarian theories consider the practice of promising to be a tool for increasing social welfare. The premises of each of these theories seem to rule out the possibility of promises to unidentified individuals. Accordingly, reflections on this topic may some shed light on some problems related to the issue of the identifiability effect, which is widely discussed in the psychological literature.
The research on this article was funded by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education in Poland, National Program for the Development of Humanities, no. 0068/NPRH4/H2b/83/2016.
Adam Michał Dyrda
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 113 - 143
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.005.9888Analyses of the concept of law rely on certain self-evident truths: truisms (platitudes) about law that people generally share and which reflect their common understanding of this important social concept. General legal theories are products of such analyses. In this paper I argue that every reference to truisms in the context of legal theory building should also take into account inferential processes by which truisms themselves are coined, namely different types of heuristics about law and related phenomena. Since both truisms and heuristics are unstructured, often inconsistent, and even fallible, conceptual analyses are the main means of transforming such “raw” evidence into rationally structured legal theories.
This paper was written as a result of research project no. 2016/21/D/HS5/03839, financed by the Polish National Science Centre.
Przemysław Kaczmarek
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 145 - 165
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.006.9889Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 167 - 184
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.007.9890The problems associated with understanding law as the regulator of social relations involve many separate issues which undoubtedly constitute intellectual challenges for the philosophy of law. In this context, the philosophy of law inquires, inter alia, about whether law exists as a universal structure of the category of being, and about the possibility of the objective cognition of law as an ontological and deontological category. However, it transpires that this task is by no means easy, when it comes to questions concerning epistemological and ontological issues in relation to law – and consequently its justification (the metaphysics of law), and then its legitimation – unequivocal answers are not forthcoming.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/19/B/HS5/03114
Monika Zalewska
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 185 - 206
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.008.9891The article examines the cognitive, metaphorical dimension of the pure theory of law and demonstrates that Hans Kelsen used metaphorical language in his description of law, and unintentionally created a unique set of cognitive metaphors in order to make a theory of law focused on the abstract “Ought” world comprehensible. The paper argues that it would be impossible for Kelsen to describe norms without metaphors. The paper uses Lakoff and Johnson’s theory as a framework for the interpretation of this metaphorical aspect of the pure theory of law. Hence the following paragraphs will examine the cognitive context of the abstract categories crucial for the pure theory of law, such as: the category of Ought, imputation, basic norms and the dynamic (hierarchical) structure of law. This article is based on the position that an analysis of the cognitive dimension of the pure theory of law might yield promising results which could reveal new aspects of the central categories in this theory. This article is an attempt to explore the possibilities provided by merging these two theories and checking if the result brings some new knowledge about the pure theory of law and legal thinking in general.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/17/B/HS5/00495
Mariusz Jerzy Golecki
Principia, Volume 65, 2018, pp. 207 - 231
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.18.009.10868In his theory of adjudication, Aristotle observes that the judicial process should be based on rational and impartial evaluation of the merits of given case and on the application of law. This paper focuses on the bipolar character of the theory of adjudication analyzed from the perspective of the modern dual process theory. It seems that the bounded rationality of judges may create a potential threat to the impartiality and rationality of judgments in complex cases. In this context the hybrid model of categorization adopted from cognitive psychology is to be confronted with the Aristotelian theory of adjudication. The influence of heuristics and biases on judicial decisions is also to be considered. The conclusion refers to the prospects of an Aristotelian virtue-centered model of adjudication following the assumption of bounded rationality.
The research on this article was funded by the National Science Centre, Poland, no. 2015/17/B/HS5/00495
Publication date: 2017
Editor-in-Chief: Krzysztof Guczalski
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 1 - 1
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.005.9277The aim of this article is to analyse the on‑going dispute over the Constitutional Tribunal in Poland from the perspective of legal philosophy. The author first posits that an argument from the Rechtsstaat idea is inadequate for a prospective solution to this dispute, then that the dispute is based on the assumptions of outdated paradigms, such as legal positivism and post‑totalitarian models of law. In order to resolve the dispute, the author proposes reflection based on the model of a communicational concept of law and the idea of a civil community.
Carl Humphries
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 5 - 41
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.001.9273This article argues that the challenges to political legitimacy currently encountered by liberal democracies affected by populist anti-centrism imply a crisis of theoretical understanding. This is because the competing claims made by recent and contemporary political thinkers reflect common underlying assumptions that put them radically at odds with the perspectives of at least some of those now embracing political populism. As a consequence, the latter find themselves excluded from any justifications for preferring certain sorts of political institution – such as liberal-democratic ones – over others.
Joanna Klimczyk
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 43 - 80
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.002.9274In his article ‘Is Meaning Fraught with Ought?’ (2009), Daniel Whiting advanced quite a battery of refurbished arguments for the claim that linguistic meaning is intrinsically normative. He ended the paper with the conclusion that he had managed to achieve two of his stated aims: to defend normativism and to show how the normativist can turn the innocent platitude that meaningful expressions possess conditions of correct use into an argument in favour of normativism. In the present article, I show that Whiting failed on both counts, although his failure reveals an important issue which has been overlooked by both parties to the debate. The issue in question is one of methodology: to wit, the plausibility of semantic normativism turns on the theory of practical normativity to which a particular philosopher tacitly or explicitly subscribes. To put my main criticism in a nutshell: semantic normativism cannot be defended without a plausible account of the nature of semantic reasons.
Olga Poller
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 81 - 108
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.003.9275This article is the second part of my defence of a non-classical descriptive theory of reference-fixing for proper names against objections raised by Kripke. In part I (in the previous issue), I defined the notion of descriptivism, showed how taking the parameter of time into account influences the formulation of theses of descriptivism and explained why Kripke’s modal objection does not apply to descriptive theory of reference. I then formulated theses of the defended descriptive theory of reference-fixing and answered Kripke’s epistemic objection. In this paper, I answer Kripke’s semantic objection against descriptivism, considered to be his strongest and most persuasive argumentation (Salmon 2005, p. 29), because it concerns the use of proper names in simple contexts without epistemic or modal operators. The semantic objection consists of a number of arguments, which I answer in turn. In section II.1, I explain the notion of knowledge required by the defended version of descriptivism. Next I argue that the only moments when knowledge of descriptions is required are those when a name is bestowed or learned, and I show that, in light of the defended theory, knowledge of descriptions at those moments is necessary and sufficient for knowing a name. In section II.2, I answer all the strands of the semantic objection. In section II.3, I show that the defended version of descriptivism has all the virtues traditionally associated with descriptive theories.
Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 109 - 154
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.004.9276In this article, I show that contemporary individualism is strongly rooted in Christian thinking about the person (divine and human). I endeavour to demonstrate the gradual aspiration to the utmost individualisation and separation of the human subject, beginning with the first definitions of the person. I outline the process of self-authorisation, whereby moral and cognitive powers formerly ascribed to God are transferred to the human subject. That process ultimately leads to (divine) transcendence becoming fixed in (human) immanence, and so to the full individualisation of the subject. In this article, I focus in particular on St Thomas Aquinas, generally seen as a precursor of personalism, and on Søren Kierkegaard, as a thinker in whom one can observe almost first-hand the emergence of self-authorisation and its various consequences. I end by looking at individualism and singularity in terms of mythology and the myth of Western culture, yet grounded on real existential foundations.
Maciej Kijko
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 201 - 223
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.006.9278This article is a polemic with Roman Godlewski’s text on Donald Davidson’s theory of interpretation and with his critique of Jerzy Kmita’s reading of the American neo-pragmatist’s ideas. The aim of this article is to rebut the arguments against Kmita’s proposed interpretation of Davidson’s theory. I find those arguments to be inconclusive, in some cases even inadequate, and I formulate a strengthening of Kmita’s standpoint.
Anna Alichniewicz, Monika Michałowska
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 225 - 255
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.007.9279This article surveys the main issues of definitions and argumentation relating to the debate over human enhancement. We note the existence of a sort of notional cascade: seeking to provide a definition of enhancement, authors attempt to distinguish it from therapy. Defining therapy requires the notion of normality, which in turn refers – explicitly or implicitly – to the notion of human nature. In this article, 1) we present the complexity and lack of clarity displayed by the notion of enhancement 2) we analyse the main arguments in favour of distinguishing the notions of “therapy” and “enhancement”, 3) we analyse the notion of normality, 4) we refer to problems of interpretation relating to the notion of “human nature”, 5) noting that fears over human enhancement are grounded on the phenomenon known as neophobia, we explore that phenomenon in one of its manifestations, 6) we outline the issue of criteria for the categorisation and classification of methods of enhancement – a problem embroiled in a number of implicit assumptions.
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 1 - 1
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.005.9277The aim of this article is to analyse the on‑going dispute over the Constitutional Tribunal in Poland from the perspective of legal philosophy. The author first posits that an argument from the Rechtsstaat idea is inadequate for a prospective solution to this dispute, then that the dispute is based on the assumptions of outdated paradigms, such as legal positivism and post‑totalitarian models of law. In order to resolve the dispute, the author proposes reflection based on the model of a communicational concept of law and the idea of a civil community.
Carl Humphries
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 5 - 41
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.001.9273This article argues that the challenges to political legitimacy currently encountered by liberal democracies affected by populist anti-centrism imply a crisis of theoretical understanding. This is because the competing claims made by recent and contemporary political thinkers reflect common underlying assumptions that put them radically at odds with the perspectives of at least some of those now embracing political populism. As a consequence, the latter find themselves excluded from any justifications for preferring certain sorts of political institution – such as liberal-democratic ones – over others.
Joanna Klimczyk
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 43 - 80
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.002.9274In his article ‘Is Meaning Fraught with Ought?’ (2009), Daniel Whiting advanced quite a battery of refurbished arguments for the claim that linguistic meaning is intrinsically normative. He ended the paper with the conclusion that he had managed to achieve two of his stated aims: to defend normativism and to show how the normativist can turn the innocent platitude that meaningful expressions possess conditions of correct use into an argument in favour of normativism. In the present article, I show that Whiting failed on both counts, although his failure reveals an important issue which has been overlooked by both parties to the debate. The issue in question is one of methodology: to wit, the plausibility of semantic normativism turns on the theory of practical normativity to which a particular philosopher tacitly or explicitly subscribes. To put my main criticism in a nutshell: semantic normativism cannot be defended without a plausible account of the nature of semantic reasons.
Olga Poller
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 81 - 108
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.003.9275This article is the second part of my defence of a non-classical descriptive theory of reference-fixing for proper names against objections raised by Kripke. In part I (in the previous issue), I defined the notion of descriptivism, showed how taking the parameter of time into account influences the formulation of theses of descriptivism and explained why Kripke’s modal objection does not apply to descriptive theory of reference. I then formulated theses of the defended descriptive theory of reference-fixing and answered Kripke’s epistemic objection. In this paper, I answer Kripke’s semantic objection against descriptivism, considered to be his strongest and most persuasive argumentation (Salmon 2005, p. 29), because it concerns the use of proper names in simple contexts without epistemic or modal operators. The semantic objection consists of a number of arguments, which I answer in turn. In section II.1, I explain the notion of knowledge required by the defended version of descriptivism. Next I argue that the only moments when knowledge of descriptions is required are those when a name is bestowed or learned, and I show that, in light of the defended theory, knowledge of descriptions at those moments is necessary and sufficient for knowing a name. In section II.2, I answer all the strands of the semantic objection. In section II.3, I show that the defended version of descriptivism has all the virtues traditionally associated with descriptive theories.
Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 109 - 154
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.004.9276In this article, I show that contemporary individualism is strongly rooted in Christian thinking about the person (divine and human). I endeavour to demonstrate the gradual aspiration to the utmost individualisation and separation of the human subject, beginning with the first definitions of the person. I outline the process of self-authorisation, whereby moral and cognitive powers formerly ascribed to God are transferred to the human subject. That process ultimately leads to (divine) transcendence becoming fixed in (human) immanence, and so to the full individualisation of the subject. In this article, I focus in particular on St Thomas Aquinas, generally seen as a precursor of personalism, and on Søren Kierkegaard, as a thinker in whom one can observe almost first-hand the emergence of self-authorisation and its various consequences. I end by looking at individualism and singularity in terms of mythology and the myth of Western culture, yet grounded on real existential foundations.
Maciej Kijko
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 201 - 223
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.006.9278This article is a polemic with Roman Godlewski’s text on Donald Davidson’s theory of interpretation and with his critique of Jerzy Kmita’s reading of the American neo-pragmatist’s ideas. The aim of this article is to rebut the arguments against Kmita’s proposed interpretation of Davidson’s theory. I find those arguments to be inconclusive, in some cases even inadequate, and I formulate a strengthening of Kmita’s standpoint.
Anna Alichniewicz, Monika Michałowska
Principia, Volume 64, 2017, pp. 225 - 255
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.17.007.9279This article surveys the main issues of definitions and argumentation relating to the debate over human enhancement. We note the existence of a sort of notional cascade: seeking to provide a definition of enhancement, authors attempt to distinguish it from therapy. Defining therapy requires the notion of normality, which in turn refers – explicitly or implicitly – to the notion of human nature. In this article, 1) we present the complexity and lack of clarity displayed by the notion of enhancement 2) we analyse the main arguments in favour of distinguishing the notions of “therapy” and “enhancement”, 3) we analyse the notion of normality, 4) we refer to problems of interpretation relating to the notion of “human nature”, 5) noting that fears over human enhancement are grounded on the phenomenon known as neophobia, we explore that phenomenon in one of its manifestations, 6) we outline the issue of criteria for the categorisation and classification of methods of enhancement – a problem embroiled in a number of implicit assumptions.
Publication date: 2016
Editor-in-Chief: Krzysztof Guczalski
Volume Editors: Krzysztof Guczalski, Steffen Huber, Jacek Rabus, Leszek Wroński
Alexander Wilfing
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 5 - 35
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.001.7640In this paper, I argue for an implicit version of ‘enhanced formalism’ in Eduard Hanslick´s aesthetics, usually misread as ‘extreme’ formalism devoid of any positive account of emotion and music. I outline ‘enhanced formalism’ in its contemporary incarnations (Davies, Kivy), explore certain common features with Hanslick’s approach, and finally explain why the concept of expressive properties as intrinsic properties of musical structure was ultimately abandoned by Hanslick.
Andrzej Nowakowski
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 37 - 61
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.002.7641There is a contradiction in our general picture of the world, brought about by the principle of causality and the metaphysical interpretation of the assertion that we are independent originators of our acts. In this paper, I consider various ways of removing that contradiction. The way that I regard as the best, however, requires the solving of a certain problem, namely, that it is necessary to account for the relationship between acts of thinking and the contents of thoughts, including between acts of deciding and the contents of reasons behind decisions. This is a difficult problem, but the problems generated by other ways of removing the contradiction are more difficult still.
Ewa Rosiak-Zięba
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 63 - 83
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.003.7642During the twentieth century, the term ‘relativity’ enjoyed considerable popularity, not only in the field of physics, but also in the humanities (although not necessarily drawing on the same inspirations). In the domain of philosophy, relativism is not a new concept; its precursors can be found in ancient Greece. Yet during the twentieth century, new stimuli for its development appeared. At the same time, however, relativism was subjected to severe criticism. In this paper, I discuss some of the issues relating to this philosophical current. The essay consists of two parts. The first part provides a general characterisation of the concept of relativism – with particular emphasis on the question of what might constitute its principal thesis. The second part deals with selected difficulties related to relativism.
Olga Poller
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 85 - 108
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.004.7643Łukasz Kołoczek
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 109 - 130
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.005.7644In the present article, I enter into a discussion with Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz’s proposed translations included in his book Formy istnienia [Forms of existence]. They concern Martin Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit and depart from the Polish tradition of translating Heidegger. Rymkiewicz proposes translating Sein as ‘istnienie’ (rather than ‘bycie’), and Dasein as ‘przebywanie’. Although not justifying his decisions, the author does put forward an elaborate interpretation of Heidegger’s work in the new terminology. The present article explores the reading of Heidegger that Rymkiewicz propounds by means of these different translations. I argue that his interpretation is at odds with Heidegger’s conception. Rymkiewicz places great emphasis on the phenomenological side of Heidegger’s project, failing to appreciate its hermeneutical component. As a consequence, he treats existence as given, which, although perhaps justified in phenomenological terms, entirely misses the point of Heidegger’s idea of Sein. That is the fundamental accusation against the term ‘istnienie’. I also reveal inconsistencies in these propositions as they appear on other levels of Heidegger’s text.
Kamil Moroz
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 131 - 162
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.006.7645The aim of this article is to analyse possible experience in Franz Brentano’s Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. The analytical and integral study of possible mental experiences allows us to discern a transcendental premise in empirically orientated psychology. The ambiguity of Brentano’s project is most fully manifest in the problem of subjectivity: it is approached from an empirical (the subject as such and not some other intentional bundle or subjectivity as a point on the map of possible references) and transcendental perspective (the subject as a condition of every intentional bundle or subjectivity as enabling the map of experience to be drawn). We find neither a formulation nor a solution to this ambiguity on the pages of the young Brentano’s philosophical treatise: they remain in the hands of the reader drawing on the tools of his Psychology.
Paweł Dybel
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 163 - 200
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.009.7812The problem of how to apprehend the relationship between the human body, its physiological basis and human mental life has been the object of fiery philosophical debate for centuries. In modern psychiatry and psychotherapy, it revolves around the question of the extent to which human mental life is autonomous or is determined by the physiological processes of the human body. This dispute is not confined to the strictly anthropological dimension; it concerns also the question of the psychiatrist’s choice of an appropriate method of therapy for a patient. In this article, I present the standpoint adopted on this issue by Roman Markuszewicz, a prominent psychoanalytically-oriented Polish psychiatrist in the period between the two world wars. He was critical both of traditional forms of therapy ‘through faith’ and also of modern forms of therapy based on psychosurgery and pharmacotherapy. I discuss his main objections to these two different forms of therapy and his arguments for the effectiveness of a Freudian model of therapy based on dialogue with the patient and on an attempt to transform his self-understanding.
Joanna Rak
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 201 - 224
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.007.7646The typology of revitalisation movements is still an unresolved problem in the specialist literature. This paper presents a critical analysis of the different takes on irredentism and of its contradictory ideal types, as well as a description, interpretation and critique of each theoretical proposition. Those of proven weakness were replaced with new, original concepts. The new types of irredentism and counter-irredentism were formulated in accordance with an homogeneous set of criteria for the direction and degree of valorisation of the homeland. Together they make up a typology that is a useful tool for describing the political thought of populations influenced by globalisation with regard to their attitudes towards the homeland. The empirical verification of the effectiveness of this typology appears to be an interesting challenge for scholars studying contemporary political thought. However, it is worth criticising, modifying or supplementing that perspective, since the proposed types are not definitive. Critical discussion of their meanings could help expand our knowledge of political reality.
Mateusz Stępień
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 225 - 249
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.008.7647The aim of this paper is to reconstruct Confucian reflections on law. Interestingly, even such a general aim has not previously been realised. Stereotypical, literal and oversimplified readings of Confucianism seem to dominate even in the professional literature. As a result, the thesis of the anti-legal character of Confucian teachings is widely reiterated. In this paper, a reconstruction of the Confucian approach to law takes account of the most basic assumptions organising Confucian thought. Only in this way can we identify the essential themes of Confucian reflection on law: (1) placing law within an ontology of the social world based on categories of ‘roots-foundations’ (ben) and ‘branches-manifestations’ (mo) and (2) considering the impact of law on the self-cultivation processes which are, according to Confucianists, the ‘root-foundation’.
Alexander Wilfing
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 5 - 35
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.001.7640In this paper, I argue for an implicit version of ‘enhanced formalism’ in Eduard Hanslick´s aesthetics, usually misread as ‘extreme’ formalism devoid of any positive account of emotion and music. I outline ‘enhanced formalism’ in its contemporary incarnations (Davies, Kivy), explore certain common features with Hanslick’s approach, and finally explain why the concept of expressive properties as intrinsic properties of musical structure was ultimately abandoned by Hanslick.
Andrzej Nowakowski
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 37 - 61
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.002.7641There is a contradiction in our general picture of the world, brought about by the principle of causality and the metaphysical interpretation of the assertion that we are independent originators of our acts. In this paper, I consider various ways of removing that contradiction. The way that I regard as the best, however, requires the solving of a certain problem, namely, that it is necessary to account for the relationship between acts of thinking and the contents of thoughts, including between acts of deciding and the contents of reasons behind decisions. This is a difficult problem, but the problems generated by other ways of removing the contradiction are more difficult still.
Ewa Rosiak-Zięba
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 63 - 83
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.003.7642During the twentieth century, the term ‘relativity’ enjoyed considerable popularity, not only in the field of physics, but also in the humanities (although not necessarily drawing on the same inspirations). In the domain of philosophy, relativism is not a new concept; its precursors can be found in ancient Greece. Yet during the twentieth century, new stimuli for its development appeared. At the same time, however, relativism was subjected to severe criticism. In this paper, I discuss some of the issues relating to this philosophical current. The essay consists of two parts. The first part provides a general characterisation of the concept of relativism – with particular emphasis on the question of what might constitute its principal thesis. The second part deals with selected difficulties related to relativism.
Olga Poller
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 85 - 108
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.004.7643Łukasz Kołoczek
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 109 - 130
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.005.7644In the present article, I enter into a discussion with Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz’s proposed translations included in his book Formy istnienia [Forms of existence]. They concern Martin Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit and depart from the Polish tradition of translating Heidegger. Rymkiewicz proposes translating Sein as ‘istnienie’ (rather than ‘bycie’), and Dasein as ‘przebywanie’. Although not justifying his decisions, the author does put forward an elaborate interpretation of Heidegger’s work in the new terminology. The present article explores the reading of Heidegger that Rymkiewicz propounds by means of these different translations. I argue that his interpretation is at odds with Heidegger’s conception. Rymkiewicz places great emphasis on the phenomenological side of Heidegger’s project, failing to appreciate its hermeneutical component. As a consequence, he treats existence as given, which, although perhaps justified in phenomenological terms, entirely misses the point of Heidegger’s idea of Sein. That is the fundamental accusation against the term ‘istnienie’. I also reveal inconsistencies in these propositions as they appear on other levels of Heidegger’s text.
Kamil Moroz
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 131 - 162
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.006.7645The aim of this article is to analyse possible experience in Franz Brentano’s Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. The analytical and integral study of possible mental experiences allows us to discern a transcendental premise in empirically orientated psychology. The ambiguity of Brentano’s project is most fully manifest in the problem of subjectivity: it is approached from an empirical (the subject as such and not some other intentional bundle or subjectivity as a point on the map of possible references) and transcendental perspective (the subject as a condition of every intentional bundle or subjectivity as enabling the map of experience to be drawn). We find neither a formulation nor a solution to this ambiguity on the pages of the young Brentano’s philosophical treatise: they remain in the hands of the reader drawing on the tools of his Psychology.
Paweł Dybel
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 163 - 200
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.009.7812The problem of how to apprehend the relationship between the human body, its physiological basis and human mental life has been the object of fiery philosophical debate for centuries. In modern psychiatry and psychotherapy, it revolves around the question of the extent to which human mental life is autonomous or is determined by the physiological processes of the human body. This dispute is not confined to the strictly anthropological dimension; it concerns also the question of the psychiatrist’s choice of an appropriate method of therapy for a patient. In this article, I present the standpoint adopted on this issue by Roman Markuszewicz, a prominent psychoanalytically-oriented Polish psychiatrist in the period between the two world wars. He was critical both of traditional forms of therapy ‘through faith’ and also of modern forms of therapy based on psychosurgery and pharmacotherapy. I discuss his main objections to these two different forms of therapy and his arguments for the effectiveness of a Freudian model of therapy based on dialogue with the patient and on an attempt to transform his self-understanding.
Joanna Rak
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 201 - 224
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.007.7646The typology of revitalisation movements is still an unresolved problem in the specialist literature. This paper presents a critical analysis of the different takes on irredentism and of its contradictory ideal types, as well as a description, interpretation and critique of each theoretical proposition. Those of proven weakness were replaced with new, original concepts. The new types of irredentism and counter-irredentism were formulated in accordance with an homogeneous set of criteria for the direction and degree of valorisation of the homeland. Together they make up a typology that is a useful tool for describing the political thought of populations influenced by globalisation with regard to their attitudes towards the homeland. The empirical verification of the effectiveness of this typology appears to be an interesting challenge for scholars studying contemporary political thought. However, it is worth criticising, modifying or supplementing that perspective, since the proposed types are not definitive. Critical discussion of their meanings could help expand our knowledge of political reality.
Mateusz Stępień
Principia, Volume 63, 2016, pp. 225 - 249
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.16.008.7647The aim of this paper is to reconstruct Confucian reflections on law. Interestingly, even such a general aim has not previously been realised. Stereotypical, literal and oversimplified readings of Confucianism seem to dominate even in the professional literature. As a result, the thesis of the anti-legal character of Confucian teachings is widely reiterated. In this paper, a reconstruction of the Confucian approach to law takes account of the most basic assumptions organising Confucian thought. Only in this way can we identify the essential themes of Confucian reflection on law: (1) placing law within an ontology of the social world based on categories of ‘roots-foundations’ (ben) and ‘branches-manifestations’ (mo) and (2) considering the impact of law on the self-cultivation processes which are, according to Confucianists, the ‘root-foundation’.
Publication date: 2016
Editor-in-Chief: Krzysztof Guczalski
Volume Editors: Tomasz Bekrycht, Jacek Rabus
Jan Woleński
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 5 - 18
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.001.5530The aim of this article is to analyse Radbruch's formula (lex iniustissima non est lex) with regard to the notions it contains and to indicate that it expresses a basic problem of philosophy of law linked to the discussion between legal positivism and the doctrines of natural law. That analysis underpins the proposal for a possible rational compromise between the two standpoints. The main problem in the dispute between the rival doctrines amounts to the adoption of some material criterion for defining gross injustice, whilst the background to the dispute is the functioning of the principle which states that law is not retroactive.
Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 19 - 40
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.002.5531The purpose of this paper is to present a metaphysical analysis of one of the main theses of legal positivism, namely that legal facts are ultimately determined by social facts alone. A short analysis of the notions of social and legal facts is followed by a presentation of possible accounts of the relation of determination. Three alternative accounts are discussed: the reduction of legal facts to social facts, the supervenience of legal facts on social facts and the grounding of legal facts by social facts. The first and second accounts are dismissed as unsatisfactory. The account of determination as a relation of metaphysical grounding appears to be promising, but creates difficulties with explaining the normative nature of legal facts.
Jerzy Leszczyński
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 41 - 54
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.003.5532Constructing a normative theory of legal interpretation involves difficulties of various types. One problem is the adoption of certain cognitive assumptions concerning the choice of the legal articles that are subject to interpretation. Another difficulty is ascertaining what determines the rationality of the interpretive activities pursued in accordance with the proposed directives of interpretation. The third obstacle is the need to harmonise the theory of legal interpretation with the dialogical nature of understanding on one hand, and with the historicity of legal discourse on the other.
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 55 - 88
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.004.5533This paper explores the tension between ethics and law in the theory of Emmanuel Lévinas. Institutions and ethics have different relations with individuals in their ‘uniqueness’ and ‘legal subjectivity’. After unmasking the ambivalence of positive law, Lévinas issued a robust appeal for laws to be anchored in civic discourse. They should also be orientated towards the pre-original rights of man. In Lévinas’s writings, the notions of justice and the ‘Third’ become increasingly important. The author has followed that evolution and sketched the framework of a sceptical philosophyof law according to Lévinas, irrespective of his apparent predilection for unconditional ethics.
Adam Sulikowski
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 89 - 106
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.005.5534The author uses the Nietzschean metaphor of the death of God to depict the condition of modern jurisprudence, which, hitherto based on the positivist paradigm, must now deal with anti-foundationalist and sceptical tendencies in contemporary philosophy.
Jadwiga Potrzeszcz
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 107 - 122
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.006.5535
The objective of this article is to provide an answer to the question: ‘Is there an essential relationship between the weighing of values in law and the rejection of the possibility of the existence of absolute values?’ In other words, we can ask whether the fact alone of weighing values in law implies the relativity of these values.
The author, following Heinrich Hubmann, proposes a distinction between the absoluteness of values themselves and the relativisation of their weight in an instance of specific application. She argues that the weighing of values does not exclude the existence of absolute values and that the feature of absoluteness belongs to basic and widely applicable values. However, in an instance where conflict arises between them, their weight may vary, depending on the specific circumstances.
The author concludes that relativisation concerns not a value itself, which remains an absolute value, but its weight within the context of the requirements of different values and the requirements stemming from the nature of things.
Tatiana Chauvin
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 123 - 142
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.007.5536The aim of this text is to challenge the tendency, discernible in legal discourse, to limit the vision of man as a legal subject to the construction of a natural person. As a category of private law, the subjectivity of the natural person cannot reflect the complexity of the relationships in which a man functions in the domain regulated by law or take into account the features that characterise him with regard to law. Hence the author attempts to construct another, more universal, model of human legal personality, which can be reliably applied to the whole of the law
Anna Młynarska-Sobaczewska
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 143 - 158
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.008.5537In this article, the author discusses the irreducibility of the norms of human rights to the rules of logic and to a syllogistic model for the application of law. She discusses the proposal of applying hermeneutical method to the process of adjudication, which could lead to a correspondence between the meanings of legal facts and norms.
Mariusz Jerzy Golecki
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 159 - 176
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.009.5538This paper concerns the relationship between the development of the doctrine of binding precedent in English jurisprudence and the evolution of British legal positivism, with particular focus on the development of judicial practice and the search for the ultimate criteria of validity. Based on examples from English judicial practice, the article explores the dilemmas of imperative legal theory. The proposed hypothesis is based on the assumption that the evolution of the doctrine of binding precedent in English law became an essential factor behind refined legal positivism in general and the concept of the rule of recognition in particular.
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 177 - 203
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.010.5539This article focuses on the conceptual analysis of law and morality from the perspective of their relationship with the concepts of violence and coercion. The author conducts a phenomenological analysis of the concepts of law and morality, pointing out their ambiguity and the difficulties with defining their mutual relations. This analysis leads to the conclusion that three phenomena (law, morality and positive law) must be taken into consideration for those relations to be correctly defined. This allows the content of positive law to be shielded against dogmatism and ideologies. The author also challenges the thesis of a special role of morality in social relationships and strongly emphasises the crucial, primary role of positive law in those relations
Maciej Pichlak
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 205 - 224
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.011.5540The aim of this article is to present Kaarlo Tuori’s theory of law termed Critical Legal Positivism (CLP). It outlines the fundamental claims of CLP with regard to law, conceiving law as a complex, dialectical concept combining the opposing (to some extent) elements described in legal tradition as ratio and voluntas (rational standards and political will). According to CLP, this complexity is best represented by a theoretical model of law as a multi-layered order, containing a surface layer (positive law), a legal culture and a ‘deep culture’. All three layers, according to a positivistic account, are regarded as socially created, yet they differ in their nature and in the way they come into being. A reconstruction of those layers is followed by analysis of the main functions of the deeper levels of legal order. On one hand, those deeper strata are said to discharge a limiting and critical role (they restrict the discretionary will of law-making and law-applying authorities); on the other, they constitute and legitimise positive law. By the same token, they serve as a medium between law and public opinion.
Katarzyna Eliasz, Wojciech Załuski
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 225 - 237
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.013.5542The concept of legal validity is regarded within the dominant legal-positivistic account of law as a non-gradable concept: a legal rule is either valid or non-valid. However, this account of validity is criticised by some scholars for being too strict and rigid. An attractive alternative would appear to be offered by Alf Ross’s account of validity as a probabilistic concept. Ross assumed that the stronger the predictions of judicial behaviour that a given rule generates, the higher the probability that can be assigned to its validity. However, this account of legal validity is by no means uncontroversial. In this paper, four objections against it are formulated: apparent gradability, problematic ascertainability, the normative insignificance of probabilistic information and the neglecting of the normativity of legal rules. These objections are treated in this paper as strong grounds for rejecting Ross’s claim that predictions of judicial behaviour formulated on the basis of rules are conceptually linked to their validity (i.e. they define their meaning); it is argued in the paper that they are merely a way of testing empirical hypotheses concerning the application (effectiveness) of legal rules.
Adam Michał Dyrda
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 239 - 262
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.014.5543The subject of this paper is the status of the most fundamental legal disagreements. Since all legal disagreements are conceptually dependent on theoretical assumptions about law (the grounds of law), they should be seen as theoretical disagreements in the Dworkinean sense. After an analysis of the basic concepts of the grounds of law, theoretical disagreements are evaluated from the epistemic point of view. By assumption, all philosophical disagreements, including fundamental legal disagreements, are disagreements between epistemic peers, since there occurs a symmetry between the evidence in favour of each of the proposed theories. In order to avoid the scepticism that such a diagnosis may lead to, we should engage in pragmatic considerations of the status of legal theory in general.
Jan Woleński
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 5 - 18
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.001.5530The aim of this article is to analyse Radbruch's formula (lex iniustissima non est lex) with regard to the notions it contains and to indicate that it expresses a basic problem of philosophy of law linked to the discussion between legal positivism and the doctrines of natural law. That analysis underpins the proposal for a possible rational compromise between the two standpoints. The main problem in the dispute between the rival doctrines amounts to the adoption of some material criterion for defining gross injustice, whilst the background to the dispute is the functioning of the principle which states that law is not retroactive.
Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 19 - 40
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.002.5531The purpose of this paper is to present a metaphysical analysis of one of the main theses of legal positivism, namely that legal facts are ultimately determined by social facts alone. A short analysis of the notions of social and legal facts is followed by a presentation of possible accounts of the relation of determination. Three alternative accounts are discussed: the reduction of legal facts to social facts, the supervenience of legal facts on social facts and the grounding of legal facts by social facts. The first and second accounts are dismissed as unsatisfactory. The account of determination as a relation of metaphysical grounding appears to be promising, but creates difficulties with explaining the normative nature of legal facts.
Jerzy Leszczyński
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 41 - 54
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.003.5532Constructing a normative theory of legal interpretation involves difficulties of various types. One problem is the adoption of certain cognitive assumptions concerning the choice of the legal articles that are subject to interpretation. Another difficulty is ascertaining what determines the rationality of the interpretive activities pursued in accordance with the proposed directives of interpretation. The third obstacle is the need to harmonise the theory of legal interpretation with the dialogical nature of understanding on one hand, and with the historicity of legal discourse on the other.
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 55 - 88
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.004.5533This paper explores the tension between ethics and law in the theory of Emmanuel Lévinas. Institutions and ethics have different relations with individuals in their ‘uniqueness’ and ‘legal subjectivity’. After unmasking the ambivalence of positive law, Lévinas issued a robust appeal for laws to be anchored in civic discourse. They should also be orientated towards the pre-original rights of man. In Lévinas’s writings, the notions of justice and the ‘Third’ become increasingly important. The author has followed that evolution and sketched the framework of a sceptical philosophyof law according to Lévinas, irrespective of his apparent predilection for unconditional ethics.
Adam Sulikowski
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 89 - 106
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.005.5534The author uses the Nietzschean metaphor of the death of God to depict the condition of modern jurisprudence, which, hitherto based on the positivist paradigm, must now deal with anti-foundationalist and sceptical tendencies in contemporary philosophy.
Jadwiga Potrzeszcz
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 107 - 122
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.006.5535
The objective of this article is to provide an answer to the question: ‘Is there an essential relationship between the weighing of values in law and the rejection of the possibility of the existence of absolute values?’ In other words, we can ask whether the fact alone of weighing values in law implies the relativity of these values.
The author, following Heinrich Hubmann, proposes a distinction between the absoluteness of values themselves and the relativisation of their weight in an instance of specific application. She argues that the weighing of values does not exclude the existence of absolute values and that the feature of absoluteness belongs to basic and widely applicable values. However, in an instance where conflict arises between them, their weight may vary, depending on the specific circumstances.
The author concludes that relativisation concerns not a value itself, which remains an absolute value, but its weight within the context of the requirements of different values and the requirements stemming from the nature of things.
Tatiana Chauvin
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 123 - 142
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.007.5536The aim of this text is to challenge the tendency, discernible in legal discourse, to limit the vision of man as a legal subject to the construction of a natural person. As a category of private law, the subjectivity of the natural person cannot reflect the complexity of the relationships in which a man functions in the domain regulated by law or take into account the features that characterise him with regard to law. Hence the author attempts to construct another, more universal, model of human legal personality, which can be reliably applied to the whole of the law
Anna Młynarska-Sobaczewska
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 143 - 158
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.008.5537In this article, the author discusses the irreducibility of the norms of human rights to the rules of logic and to a syllogistic model for the application of law. She discusses the proposal of applying hermeneutical method to the process of adjudication, which could lead to a correspondence between the meanings of legal facts and norms.
Mariusz Jerzy Golecki
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 159 - 176
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.009.5538This paper concerns the relationship between the development of the doctrine of binding precedent in English jurisprudence and the evolution of British legal positivism, with particular focus on the development of judicial practice and the search for the ultimate criteria of validity. Based on examples from English judicial practice, the article explores the dilemmas of imperative legal theory. The proposed hypothesis is based on the assumption that the evolution of the doctrine of binding precedent in English law became an essential factor behind refined legal positivism in general and the concept of the rule of recognition in particular.
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 177 - 203
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.010.5539This article focuses on the conceptual analysis of law and morality from the perspective of their relationship with the concepts of violence and coercion. The author conducts a phenomenological analysis of the concepts of law and morality, pointing out their ambiguity and the difficulties with defining their mutual relations. This analysis leads to the conclusion that three phenomena (law, morality and positive law) must be taken into consideration for those relations to be correctly defined. This allows the content of positive law to be shielded against dogmatism and ideologies. The author also challenges the thesis of a special role of morality in social relationships and strongly emphasises the crucial, primary role of positive law in those relations
Maciej Pichlak
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 205 - 224
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.011.5540The aim of this article is to present Kaarlo Tuori’s theory of law termed Critical Legal Positivism (CLP). It outlines the fundamental claims of CLP with regard to law, conceiving law as a complex, dialectical concept combining the opposing (to some extent) elements described in legal tradition as ratio and voluntas (rational standards and political will). According to CLP, this complexity is best represented by a theoretical model of law as a multi-layered order, containing a surface layer (positive law), a legal culture and a ‘deep culture’. All three layers, according to a positivistic account, are regarded as socially created, yet they differ in their nature and in the way they come into being. A reconstruction of those layers is followed by analysis of the main functions of the deeper levels of legal order. On one hand, those deeper strata are said to discharge a limiting and critical role (they restrict the discretionary will of law-making and law-applying authorities); on the other, they constitute and legitimise positive law. By the same token, they serve as a medium between law and public opinion.
Katarzyna Eliasz, Wojciech Załuski
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 225 - 237
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.013.5542The concept of legal validity is regarded within the dominant legal-positivistic account of law as a non-gradable concept: a legal rule is either valid or non-valid. However, this account of validity is criticised by some scholars for being too strict and rigid. An attractive alternative would appear to be offered by Alf Ross’s account of validity as a probabilistic concept. Ross assumed that the stronger the predictions of judicial behaviour that a given rule generates, the higher the probability that can be assigned to its validity. However, this account of legal validity is by no means uncontroversial. In this paper, four objections against it are formulated: apparent gradability, problematic ascertainability, the normative insignificance of probabilistic information and the neglecting of the normativity of legal rules. These objections are treated in this paper as strong grounds for rejecting Ross’s claim that predictions of judicial behaviour formulated on the basis of rules are conceptually linked to their validity (i.e. they define their meaning); it is argued in the paper that they are merely a way of testing empirical hypotheses concerning the application (effectiveness) of legal rules.
Adam Michał Dyrda
Principia, Volume 61-62, 2015, pp. 239 - 262
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.15.014.5543The subject of this paper is the status of the most fundamental legal disagreements. Since all legal disagreements are conceptually dependent on theoretical assumptions about law (the grounds of law), they should be seen as theoretical disagreements in the Dworkinean sense. After an analysis of the basic concepts of the grounds of law, theoretical disagreements are evaluated from the epistemic point of view. By assumption, all philosophical disagreements, including fundamental legal disagreements, are disagreements between epistemic peers, since there occurs a symmetry between the evidence in favour of each of the proposed theories. In order to avoid the scepticism that such a diagnosis may lead to, we should engage in pragmatic considerations of the status of legal theory in general.
Publication date: 2015
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editors: Jan Hartman
Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 5 - 45
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.001.2971Piotr Makowski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 67 - 81
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.003.2973Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 101 - 114
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.005.2975Tomasz Matkowski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 115 - 127
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.006.2976Artur Jochlik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 129 - 151
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.007.2977Lotar Rasiński
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 153 - 170
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.008.2978Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 171 - 196
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.009.2979Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 197 - 228
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.010.2980Bartosz Kuźniarz
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 229 - 244
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.011.2981Jacek Uglik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 245 - 255
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.012.2982Katarzyna Guczalska
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 279 - 312
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.014.2984Anita Pacholik-Żuromska
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 313 - 327
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.015.2985Katarzyna Ł. Częścik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 329 - 345
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.016.2986Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 5 - 45
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.001.2971Piotr Makowski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 67 - 81
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.003.2973Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 101 - 114
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.005.2975Tomasz Matkowski
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 115 - 127
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.006.2976Artur Jochlik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 129 - 151
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.007.2977Lotar Rasiński
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 153 - 170
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.008.2978Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 171 - 196
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.009.2979Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 197 - 228
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.010.2980Bartosz Kuźniarz
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 229 - 244
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.011.2981Jacek Uglik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 245 - 255
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.012.2982Katarzyna Guczalska
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 279 - 312
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.014.2984Anita Pacholik-Żuromska
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 313 - 327
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.015.2985Katarzyna Ł. Częścik
Principia, Vol 59-60, 2014, pp. 329 - 345
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.016.2986Publication date: 04.03.2014
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Scientific Editors: Ewa Nowak
Volume Editor: Jan Hartman
Filozofia Publiczna: Edukacja obywateli i dyskursywność instytucji
Piotr W. Juchacz, Karolina M. Cern, Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 5 - 20
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.001.1525The paramount thesis of the article is that the issue of democratic legitimation should address the mutual interrelations between social, institutional and legal orders. The normative deficit of modern democratic polities stems from the overwhelming blindness to discursive justifications of political decisions and, in consequence, from the disregard for the necessity of enhancing moral-democratic competencies of citizens themselves. Menwhile, the moral democratic competencies condition the possibility of the widen participation of the citizenry and its empowerment. The second part of the article consists of the presentation of the idea of political philosophy as public philosophy. With reference to B. Williams two essential questions are addressed: the question of the identity of public philosophy (What is public philosophy?), and the question of the audience of public philosophy (Who is being addressed and for what purpose?). A realistically utopian character of public philosophy is stressed.
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 23 - 40
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.002.1526Teaching advanced college students in the faculty of philosophy, one can observe that they reflect on democracy at a sophistic level (Rosen calls this phenomena overprofessionalization). At the same time, most of these students have never been in the middle of a real democratic discussion. All cognitive competencies need to be developed by practicing them repeatedly. Democracy is an advanced personal, interpersonal, and social competence, not only a political framework and constitution. Lind once established the concept of democratic personality. I would like to illustrate this concept by my own discursive experiences with democratic education.
Georg Lind
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 41 - 56
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.003.1527We know today that Socrates was right and that moral orientations need not be taught as they already exist inherently in man, but that moral judgmental and discourse competence are not pre-given and must consequently be fostered. We have described here a psychologically well- founded and intensively tested method with which this can be effectively done. The most urgent task now is to offer teachers good training and further training in this and similar methods so that every student can profit from effective moral education
Mateusz Bonecki
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 57 - 75
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.004.1528The point of departure of this paper is Jürgen Habermas concept of knowledge constitutive interests and its further elaboration in the so-called reconstructive sciences. The reconstructive knowledge encompasses descriptive empirical statements, relative normative statements following from explication of cultural beliefs, and normative statements raising universal validity claims. The analysis of such model of knowledge creation leads to a conclusion that the responsibility of contemporary expert cultures is to mediate between scientific research, common-sense cultural beliefs, and moral or legal assumptions that are recognized as justified and valid
Anna Malitowska
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 77 - 92
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.005.1529In the following considerations the author addresses the issue of teachers' professional ethics and in particular the issue of teachers ethical competence which is understood as a capacity to make responsible moral judgments with regard to situations that occur in the course of professional practice. In accordance with the pragmatic idea of community of inquiry, the author argues that the role of professional ethics is to design the discourse concerned with moral problems which should allow the teachers to develop and cultivate ethical competences.
Antanas Mockus
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 95 - 119
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.006.1530This essay is organized into seven sections. First, the main thesis is introduced: Democracy depends on the differentiation and harmonization of three regulatory systems: law, morality and culture. Next the argument follows that public policies depend strongly on legal changes being accompanied by changes in moral and social rules. The other sections report on the legal, moral (also motivational), and cultural education of Bogotàs citizens
Georg Lohmann
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 121 - 139
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.007.1531The article discusses the idea of universality of human rights faced with the diversity of cultures. It provides a short insight into the history of human rights institutionalisation, it also explains the meaning, scope and possible justification for the universality of human rights understood as the political project, which is morally justifiable and explicable in judicial terms. The universality and abstractness of human rights is presented as a complementary moment of individualisation of each human existence. The chief thesis is that human rights enable and admit the reconciliation of diverse, though not all, cultural practices.
Marta Soniewicka
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 141 - 164
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.008.1532The paper addresses the problem of genotypic prevention, i.e. it poses the question of whether prospective parents may be obliged to prevent the so called 'reproductive harm', caused by genetically transmitted diseases. First, the paper analyses the harm principle developed by John Stuart Mill. Second, a legal concept of harm is specified, invoking the distinction between a harmful condition and a harmed condition given by Joel Feinberg. It is argued, after Feinberg, that acts of harming must meet some specific conditions, among others there must be a person who is harmed; and either the counterfactual condition or the worsening condition. Third, the conception of prenatal harm and preconception harm is discussed and then distinguished from the so called 'reproductive harm' which is understood as harm caused by giving birth to a person which would be born in a harmful position (with a disability or a disease). The conception of 'procreative harm' poses a philosophical question concerning the non-identity problem suggested by Derek Parfit and discussed by such philosophers as Buchanan, Wikler, Brock, Daniels, Hare, Reiman, Green, Locke to name only some of them. The non-identity problem undermines the concept of procreative harm, since there is no person harmed by the procreative decision when the only alternative for a particular disabled child was not to be born. These considerations lead to the conclusion that a legal concept of 'reproductive harm' is not justified and that it should be replaced by the idea of moral procreative responsibility in the given context.
Karolina M. Cern, Bartosz Wojciechowski
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 165 - 190
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.009.1533In the following paper we investigate sources and democratic credentials of the common European constitutional culture. The significance of national constitutional traditions is contrasted with the requirement of democratic legitimation for Union law. With that regard the CJEU's ruling in case C-555/07 Seda Kücükdeveci v. Swedex GmbH&Co. KG is carefully analysed. We state a thesis that the chief feature of the searched after common European constitutional culture should be its normative emancipatory force expressed in the concept of the European self-constitutionalisation
Anna Kalisz
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 191 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.010.1534Piotr W. Juchacz
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 217 - 246
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.011.1535An article falls into the area of reflection called public philosophy and it is an example of normative analysis of functioning of the institution of public hearing introduced to Polish democratic order in 2006. Public hearing is presented as a dynamic process which consists of the three phases, with different methods, scope and purpose. An analysis focuses on the first phase, which relates to the formal and legal arrangements adopted in the Rules of the Sejm of the Republic of Poland, primarily the fundamental issue of convening a public hearing, in which author distinguishes seven problem areas that require special attention: 1) who should be allowed to table a motion to convene a public hearing? 2) should the call of a public hearing be optional or arbitrary? 3) the moment in the law-making process of convening a public hearing; 4) the problem of publicizing the decision to convene a public hearing; 5) the contents of the registration form; 6) possibility to restrict the number of participants; 7) the issue of cancellation of a public hearing.
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 247 - 268
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.012.1536The increasing complexity of the academic enterprise in Europe is due to several general factors: globalization and Europeanization, educational expansion and massification of higher education, the economic crisis, reform pressures in the public sector, growing pressures for accountability, and knowledge-driven economic competitiveness of nations and regions. Factors generating change in national higher education policies and in national higher education systems have been multilayered, interrelated and often common throughout the continent. Reforms increasingly, and throughout Europe, lead to further reforms rather than to reformed higher education systems. Higher education has changed substantially in most European economies in the last two or three decades but it is still expected by national and European-level policymakers to change even more. Universities, throughout two centuries of their modern history, change as their environments change, especially in connection with changes in the functioning of nation-states and various forms of welfare states. Different directions of current and projected academic restructuring in different national systems add to the complexity of the picture at a European level.
Paweł Jabłoński, Maciej Pichlak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 269 - 295
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.013.1537
The essay aims at analysis of the manner Polish jurisprudence perceives a role of critical perspective within legal thought. Only such critique might be plausibly called a 'reflection', since it is conducted from an internal point of view the viewpoint of legal professionals who criticize their own conceptual schemes. This analysis of theoretical projects is made in the light of sociological processes of increasing reflexivity of social practices and institutions, law included (Giddens).
The essay takes under examination four particular metaphors which are to be met in Polish jurisprudence: a lawyer as a philosopher, a lawyer as an artist, a lawyer as a participant of culture, and a lawyer as a believer. Each of them offers a slightly different answer to the question on the room for critical reflection in the law. The particular interest is paid to the way these four various theoretical proposals recognize, respectively: a significance of professional legal tradition, mutual relations between law and its social surroundings, as well as a role of individual agent in legal practice.
Michał Cichoracki
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 297 - 315
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.014.1538
The institutions are often seen as a collection of rules and norms of human behavior, organized human practices, and all sorts of his social activity implemented in the structures of meaning and identity, political system, economic growth, prescribing appropriate behavior for specific actors in specific situations or circumstances. According to this point of view the institutions can also be understand as a system of social activity's patterns maintained and reinforced for the sake of establishing, and regulating the scope, the dimension and the quality of social integration, political organization, and economic system of the production and the distribution of goods, and services.
The process of institutionalization of human life is a specific rule of the western civilization's development and makes a core of Max Weber's theory of rationalization trying to explain the most important and significant aspects of this process.
The problem is that a process of advanced human's life institutionalization leads to the symmetrically advancing bureaucratization - in some cases - in an even oligarchical way. The mutual, reciprocal causation between these two processes is a main issue in many hypotheses and theories trying to explain the structure of institutional pathologies, a lack of their - institutions - systematical flexibility or the models of their temporal and constant ineffectiveness.
Marcin Byczyński
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 317 - 328
Recenzja książki: Martha C. Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge Ma. and London 2011, s. 237
Marcin Byczyński
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 317 - 328
Recenzja książki: Martha C. Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge Ma. and London 2011, s. 237
Piotr W. Juchacz, Karolina M. Cern, Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 5 - 20
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.001.1525The paramount thesis of the article is that the issue of democratic legitimation should address the mutual interrelations between social, institutional and legal orders. The normative deficit of modern democratic polities stems from the overwhelming blindness to discursive justifications of political decisions and, in consequence, from the disregard for the necessity of enhancing moral-democratic competencies of citizens themselves. Menwhile, the moral democratic competencies condition the possibility of the widen participation of the citizenry and its empowerment. The second part of the article consists of the presentation of the idea of political philosophy as public philosophy. With reference to B. Williams two essential questions are addressed: the question of the identity of public philosophy (What is public philosophy?), and the question of the audience of public philosophy (Who is being addressed and for what purpose?). A realistically utopian character of public philosophy is stressed.
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 23 - 40
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.002.1526Teaching advanced college students in the faculty of philosophy, one can observe that they reflect on democracy at a sophistic level (Rosen calls this phenomena overprofessionalization). At the same time, most of these students have never been in the middle of a real democratic discussion. All cognitive competencies need to be developed by practicing them repeatedly. Democracy is an advanced personal, interpersonal, and social competence, not only a political framework and constitution. Lind once established the concept of democratic personality. I would like to illustrate this concept by my own discursive experiences with democratic education.
Georg Lind
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 41 - 56
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.003.1527We know today that Socrates was right and that moral orientations need not be taught as they already exist inherently in man, but that moral judgmental and discourse competence are not pre-given and must consequently be fostered. We have described here a psychologically well- founded and intensively tested method with which this can be effectively done. The most urgent task now is to offer teachers good training and further training in this and similar methods so that every student can profit from effective moral education
Mateusz Bonecki
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 57 - 75
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.004.1528The point of departure of this paper is Jürgen Habermas concept of knowledge constitutive interests and its further elaboration in the so-called reconstructive sciences. The reconstructive knowledge encompasses descriptive empirical statements, relative normative statements following from explication of cultural beliefs, and normative statements raising universal validity claims. The analysis of such model of knowledge creation leads to a conclusion that the responsibility of contemporary expert cultures is to mediate between scientific research, common-sense cultural beliefs, and moral or legal assumptions that are recognized as justified and valid
Anna Malitowska
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 77 - 92
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.005.1529In the following considerations the author addresses the issue of teachers' professional ethics and in particular the issue of teachers ethical competence which is understood as a capacity to make responsible moral judgments with regard to situations that occur in the course of professional practice. In accordance with the pragmatic idea of community of inquiry, the author argues that the role of professional ethics is to design the discourse concerned with moral problems which should allow the teachers to develop and cultivate ethical competences.
Antanas Mockus
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 95 - 119
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.006.1530This essay is organized into seven sections. First, the main thesis is introduced: Democracy depends on the differentiation and harmonization of three regulatory systems: law, morality and culture. Next the argument follows that public policies depend strongly on legal changes being accompanied by changes in moral and social rules. The other sections report on the legal, moral (also motivational), and cultural education of Bogotàs citizens
Georg Lohmann
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 121 - 139
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.007.1531The article discusses the idea of universality of human rights faced with the diversity of cultures. It provides a short insight into the history of human rights institutionalisation, it also explains the meaning, scope and possible justification for the universality of human rights understood as the political project, which is morally justifiable and explicable in judicial terms. The universality and abstractness of human rights is presented as a complementary moment of individualisation of each human existence. The chief thesis is that human rights enable and admit the reconciliation of diverse, though not all, cultural practices.
Marta Soniewicka
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 141 - 164
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.008.1532The paper addresses the problem of genotypic prevention, i.e. it poses the question of whether prospective parents may be obliged to prevent the so called 'reproductive harm', caused by genetically transmitted diseases. First, the paper analyses the harm principle developed by John Stuart Mill. Second, a legal concept of harm is specified, invoking the distinction between a harmful condition and a harmed condition given by Joel Feinberg. It is argued, after Feinberg, that acts of harming must meet some specific conditions, among others there must be a person who is harmed; and either the counterfactual condition or the worsening condition. Third, the conception of prenatal harm and preconception harm is discussed and then distinguished from the so called 'reproductive harm' which is understood as harm caused by giving birth to a person which would be born in a harmful position (with a disability or a disease). The conception of 'procreative harm' poses a philosophical question concerning the non-identity problem suggested by Derek Parfit and discussed by such philosophers as Buchanan, Wikler, Brock, Daniels, Hare, Reiman, Green, Locke to name only some of them. The non-identity problem undermines the concept of procreative harm, since there is no person harmed by the procreative decision when the only alternative for a particular disabled child was not to be born. These considerations lead to the conclusion that a legal concept of 'reproductive harm' is not justified and that it should be replaced by the idea of moral procreative responsibility in the given context.
Karolina M. Cern, Bartosz Wojciechowski
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 165 - 190
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.009.1533In the following paper we investigate sources and democratic credentials of the common European constitutional culture. The significance of national constitutional traditions is contrasted with the requirement of democratic legitimation for Union law. With that regard the CJEU's ruling in case C-555/07 Seda Kücükdeveci v. Swedex GmbH&Co. KG is carefully analysed. We state a thesis that the chief feature of the searched after common European constitutional culture should be its normative emancipatory force expressed in the concept of the European self-constitutionalisation
Anna Kalisz
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 191 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.010.1534Piotr W. Juchacz
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 217 - 246
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.011.1535An article falls into the area of reflection called public philosophy and it is an example of normative analysis of functioning of the institution of public hearing introduced to Polish democratic order in 2006. Public hearing is presented as a dynamic process which consists of the three phases, with different methods, scope and purpose. An analysis focuses on the first phase, which relates to the formal and legal arrangements adopted in the Rules of the Sejm of the Republic of Poland, primarily the fundamental issue of convening a public hearing, in which author distinguishes seven problem areas that require special attention: 1) who should be allowed to table a motion to convene a public hearing? 2) should the call of a public hearing be optional or arbitrary? 3) the moment in the law-making process of convening a public hearing; 4) the problem of publicizing the decision to convene a public hearing; 5) the contents of the registration form; 6) possibility to restrict the number of participants; 7) the issue of cancellation of a public hearing.
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 247 - 268
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.012.1536The increasing complexity of the academic enterprise in Europe is due to several general factors: globalization and Europeanization, educational expansion and massification of higher education, the economic crisis, reform pressures in the public sector, growing pressures for accountability, and knowledge-driven economic competitiveness of nations and regions. Factors generating change in national higher education policies and in national higher education systems have been multilayered, interrelated and often common throughout the continent. Reforms increasingly, and throughout Europe, lead to further reforms rather than to reformed higher education systems. Higher education has changed substantially in most European economies in the last two or three decades but it is still expected by national and European-level policymakers to change even more. Universities, throughout two centuries of their modern history, change as their environments change, especially in connection with changes in the functioning of nation-states and various forms of welfare states. Different directions of current and projected academic restructuring in different national systems add to the complexity of the picture at a European level.
Paweł Jabłoński, Maciej Pichlak
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 269 - 295
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.013.1537
The essay aims at analysis of the manner Polish jurisprudence perceives a role of critical perspective within legal thought. Only such critique might be plausibly called a 'reflection', since it is conducted from an internal point of view the viewpoint of legal professionals who criticize their own conceptual schemes. This analysis of theoretical projects is made in the light of sociological processes of increasing reflexivity of social practices and institutions, law included (Giddens).
The essay takes under examination four particular metaphors which are to be met in Polish jurisprudence: a lawyer as a philosopher, a lawyer as an artist, a lawyer as a participant of culture, and a lawyer as a believer. Each of them offers a slightly different answer to the question on the room for critical reflection in the law. The particular interest is paid to the way these four various theoretical proposals recognize, respectively: a significance of professional legal tradition, mutual relations between law and its social surroundings, as well as a role of individual agent in legal practice.
Michał Cichoracki
Principia, Vol 57-58, 2013, pp. 297 - 315
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.14.014.1538
The institutions are often seen as a collection of rules and norms of human behavior, organized human practices, and all sorts of his social activity implemented in the structures of meaning and identity, political system, economic growth, prescribing appropriate behavior for specific actors in specific situations or circumstances. According to this point of view the institutions can also be understand as a system of social activity's patterns maintained and reinforced for the sake of establishing, and regulating the scope, the dimension and the quality of social integration, political organization, and economic system of the production and the distribution of goods, and services.
The process of institutionalization of human life is a specific rule of the western civilization's development and makes a core of Max Weber's theory of rationalization trying to explain the most important and significant aspects of this process.
The problem is that a process of advanced human's life institutionalization leads to the symmetrically advancing bureaucratization - in some cases - in an even oligarchical way. The mutual, reciprocal causation between these two processes is a main issue in many hypotheses and theories trying to explain the structure of institutional pathologies, a lack of their - institutions - systematical flexibility or the models of their temporal and constant ineffectiveness.
Publication date: 04.11.2012
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editors: Jan Hartman
Grażyna Woroniecka
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 7 - 22
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.001.0577
Fragment
Pomysł, że naukowa wiedza o świecie jest konstruktem, narracją, opowieścią budzi odruchowy sprzeciw zaskakująco wielu ludzi. To, co wydaje się oczywiste socjologom wiedzy naukowej: przeświadczenie, iż wiedza jest artefaktem powstającym dzięki zbiorowej, wysoce zinstytucjonalizowanej aktywności ludzi, brzmi często jak herezja także przed uczonymi audytoriami. Sądząc po sile sprzeciwu, jaki zdarza się spotykać, jest to herezja nie jakaś nieistotna, ale taka, która wzburza do głębi, która narusza wręcz fundament wiary w to, że świat jest taki, jakim go widzimy i możemy o nim orzekać coś pewnego. Andrzej Zybertowicz ujmuje to zjawisko opisowo, w kategoriach „przeskoku” między wizjami świata, czy też „kontrintuicyjności” konstruktywistycznego modelu poznania wobec codziennej perspektywy poznawczej (Zybertowicz 1995: 122-123). Niektóre reakcje, choćby kilku moich słuchaczy na studiach doktoranckich z socjologii (sic!) wręcz zaskakiwały emocjonalną siłą kontrataku, do którego czuli się zobligowani odczytując np. tezy Bruna Latoura na temat procedur pracy laboratoryjnej jako osobisty atak na najcenniejsze wartości.
Marcin K. Zwierżdżyński
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 23 - 41
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.002.0578
Fragment
1. Teorie konstruowania w naukach społecznych
Nie ulega wątpliwości, że metaforyka konstruowania na dobre zadomowiła się we współczesnej nauce. W tych kategoriach analizowano już niemal wszystko: od samej rzeczywistości (Berger, Luckmann 1983; Manterys 1997) i nauki (Latour, Woolgar 1979; Amsterdamska 1992), przez tożsamość (Cerulo 1997; Skrendo 2004) i religię (Beckford 2003; Zwierżdżyński 2010), po płeć (Laqueur 1990; Kopciewicz 2007) i problemy społeczne (Schneider 1985; Miś 2008). Teorie konstruowania stosowane są dziś praktycznie w każdej dyscyplinie naukowej, począwszy od antropologii i socjologii (zwłaszcza analizy narratywistyczne i interakcjonistyczne, np. Bruner 1991 i Hałas 2005), psychologii i pedagogiki (np. Gergen 1985 i Klus-Stańska 2000), przez historię i archeologię (np. Gross 1986 i Ostoja-Zagórski 2000), językoznawstwo i literaturoznawstwo (np. Grace 1987 i Kuźma, Skrendo, Madejski 2006), na ekonomii i matematyce kończąc (np. Granovetter 1992 i Piotrowska 2008).
Danuta Chmielewska-Banaszak
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 43 - 63
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.003.0579
Fragment
1. Czym jest konstruktywizm w psychologii?
Konstruktywizm w psychologii nie tworzy spójnej orientacji. Ze względu na wielość teorii i koncepcji, obszerne i zróżnicowane pole badań oraz niejednorodność założeń, bardziej adekwatne wydaje się określenie „konstruktywizmy”. Uporządkowaniu wiedzy dotyczącej teorii i idei konstruktywistycznych w psychologii nie pomaga to, że można i trzeba rozpatrywać je na trzech poziomach: koncepcji dotyczących ogólnej teorii poznania, opisu teoretyczno-empirycznego oraz zastosowań praktycznych, czyli oddziaływań terapeutycznych.
Pierwszy poziom tworzą, między innymi, koncepcje Jeana Piageta, Lwa S. Wygotskiego, George’a Kelly’ego, Jeromy’ego Brunera, Kennetha J. Gergena.
Drugi poziom tworzą, oparte na konstruktywistycznych założeniach teoretyczne i empiryczne opisy funkcjonowania człowieka charakterystyczne dla różnych subdyscyplin psychologii, na przykład psychologii społecznej, psychologii emocji, psychologii osobowości czy teorii komunikacji. Dalsze części artykułu poświęcone są prezentacji konstruktywizmu w psychologii poznawczej, która zdecydowanie dominuje we współczesnej psychologii, a podejście konstruktywistyczne funkcjonuje w jej obrębie jako wiedza podręcznikowa (choć nie jest to dla psychologów poznawczych wiedza oczywista).
Agnieszka Kolasa-Nowak
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 65 - 82
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.004.0580Ewa Bińczyk
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 83 - 100
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.005.0581
Fragment
Prezentowany tu tekst składa się z dwóch części. Pierwsza z nich szkicowo kreśli parametry (właściwie dookreślonej) perspektywy konstruktywistycznej. „Właściwe” dookreślenie polega przy tym na wykorzystaniu określonych zasobów, tj. najnowszych ustaleń studiów nad nauką oraz technologią (częściowo określanych też jako socjologia wiedzy naukowej), a w tym szczególnie teorii aktora-sieci Bruno Latoura i etnografii laboratorium. W obrębie rozwijanej poniżej narracji pozycje konstruktywistyczne konstytuuje zarówno intelektualne przywiązanie do metafory „konstruowania”, jak i konglomerat akceptowanych przesądzeń, z których najważniejsze zostaną wyeksponowane.
Jak pokazuje artykuł, w odniesieniu do najnowszych rozstrzygnięć socjologii wiedzy naukowej oraz studiów nad technologią zasadne wydaje się wprowadzenie etykiety (post)konstruktywizmu. Wybrane racje przemawiające za tym posunięciem interpretacyjnym zostaną wskazane poniżej. Zagadnienie (post)konstruktywizmu w badaniach nad nauką oraz technologią nie będzie tu niestety dyskutowane w sposób pogłębiony. Zostało ono omówione szerzej gdzie indziej (por. Bińczyk 2010).
Michał Bujalski
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 101 - 115
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.006.0582Marcin K. Zwierżdżyński
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 117 - 135
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.007.0583
Fragment
Wiele jest w naukach społecznych pojęć, które można by nazwać paronimami – wystarczająco wiele, by mógł powstać ich słownik. Paronimy to słowa o zbliżonej formie, lecz różnym znaczeniu, podobnie brzmiące, utworzone na tej samej podstawie słowotwórczej, spokrewnione lub niespokrewnione etymologicznie i semantycznie, nazywane najczęściej „wyrazami mylonymi”. Na gruncie nauk społecznych można do nich zaliczyć m.in. takie pary, jak: socjobiologia i biosocjologia, postmodernizm i ponowoczesność, konsumeryzm i konsumpcjonizm, historycyzm i historyzm czy sekularyzm i sekularyzacja. Poza tymi, i wieloma innymi, również konstruktywizm i konstrukcjonizm1, jako pojęcia zdobywające ostatnio coraz więcej zwolenników, zwłaszcza wśród socjologów, psychologów i pedagogów, stosowane są często wymiennie, czasem zupełnie nieświadomie, nierzadko z zadziwiającą wręcz niekonsekwencją. Trudno określić, co decyduje każdorazowo o wyborze określonej etykiety – w grę wchodzić może gust, wygoda, popularność lub po prostu przyzwyczajenie.
Paweł Miech
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 139 - 154
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.008.0584
Fragment
Zły podmiot jest wyzwaniem dla filozofii moralnej. Etyka nie jest w stanie uznać realnej możliwości istnienia podmiotu moralnego, który byłby permanentnie i samoistnie zły. Uznanie tej możliwości wydaje się przeczyć podstawowym elementom definicji podmiotu moralnego, która stwierdza wszakże, że podmiot ten cechuje racjonalność, zdolność do uświadomienia sobie zobowiązań moralnych i wolność, która umożliwia mu poniesienie odpowiedzialności za własne poczynania. Jeśli zgodzimy się, że podmiot moralny jest z zasady świadomy prawa moralnego – musimy uznać, że jest on potencjalnie przynajmniej zdolny działania moralnego. Godząc się na tą logikę dochodzimy do wniosku, iż nawet w dogłębnie zepsutym i zdegenerowanym podmiocie istnieje potencjał do poprawy, istnieje pewien moralnie chwalebny element (np. rozum, wolność, odpowiedzialność). Zło podmiotu jest więc jedynie pewną słabością, niedoskonałością poznania lub działania wynikającą z subiektywnych lub społecznych uwarunkowań.
Przemysław Tacik
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 155 - 171
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.009.0585
Fragment
Deklarując wiarę w zadanie humanistyki w ramach bezwarunkowo otwartego uniwersytetu, Jacques Derrida1 zasugerował przedmiot, który powinien być zadaniem filozoficznej, ale i prawniczej dekonstrukcji: ideę suwerenności państwowej, we wszystkich jej powiązaniach z koncepcją obywatelstwa i praw człowieka. Nigdzie chyba władza nie przekłada się mocniej na kształtowanie definicji człowieczeństwa; nigdzie polityka nie znajduje się bliżej zsekularyzowanej teologii. Pojęcia filozoficzne przeplatają się tam z pojęciami prawnymi, zyskując walor performatywny dzięki działaniu władzy państwowej. Niniejszy artykuł stanowi próbę odpowiedzi na wezwanie, jakie rzuca filozofii idea suwerenności. By mu sprostać, filozofia musi sięgnąć nie tylko do własnych tekstów, lecz również do tekstów prawa, które w odróżnieniu od tych ostatnich – nie muszą zważać na prawdę, mają ją bowiem, wraz z władzą, po swojej stronie.
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 173 - 186
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.010.0586
Fragment
W drugiej dekadzie XXI wieku, w stwierdzeniu, że podmiot jest efektem gier władzy, użycia perswazyjnych form językowych, zabiegów ideologicznych, internalizacji stosunków dominacji etc. nie ma już nic zaskakującego. Jesteśmy dość zblazowani, aby przyjąć taką nowinę z godnością i bez mrugnięcia okiem. Teoria aparatów ideologicznych Louisa Althussera, archeologia wiedzy Michela Foucaulta, a potem rozplenienie się pasożytniczych teorii dyskursu we wszystkich jej odmianach – tej ściśle politycznej w ujęciu rozumu populistycznego Ernesto Laclaua i tej bardziej kognitywistycznej, tj. krytycznej analizy dyskursu, w ujęciu Teuna Adrianusa van Dijka, pozwala nam dziś pojmować podmiot jako zaledwie pozycję lub zbiór pozycji zajętych w sieci dyskursywnej. Mówimy sobie „tak, owszem, jesteśmy zaledwie i tylko miejscem lub zbiorem miejsc w złożonej i wielokrotnie nas przekraczającej sieci relacji znaczeń i relacji sił”. Więcej, bylibyśmy pewnie bardziej zdziwieni, gdyby komuś przyszło do głowy podważyć tę oficjalną doktrynę, której jawną intencją jest zamazanie rozróżnienia na działanie i mówienie, wiedzę o świecie (encyklopedię) oraz wiedzę o języku (leksykon), wreszcie zamazanie dystynkcji, kiedyś świętej, tj. kompetencji i wykonania, oraz – w rezultacie – teorii kompetencji czyli idealnego mówcy/słuchacza oraz teorii wykonania czyli ograniczonego i niejednorodnego językowo, zdeformowanego, spontanicznego, jąkającego się wykonawcy.
Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 187 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.011.0587
Fragment
W Narodzinach tragedii Fryderyk Nietzsche dowodził, ze sztuka teatru zawdzięcza swoje istnienie dwóm żywiołom lub raczej – jak to sam Nietzsche określał – popędom, czyli sposobom artystycznego przedstawiania rzeczywistości: dionizyjskiemu i apolińskiemu. Dionizyjskość to dla Nietzschego muzyczność – ekstatyczna amorficzność; apollińskość, z kolei, to plastyczność, pełna form i kształtów ułuda, wyśniona, by w znośnej dla człowieka postaci ukazać trudną do zniesienia dionizyjską prawdę. Prawdę tę ujawnił królowi Midasowi schwytany przezeń Sylen, towarzysz Dionizosa: „Najlepsze jest dla ciebie zupełnie nieosiągalne: nie narodzić się, nie istnieć, być niczym. Najlepsze zaś po tym jest dla ciebie – prędko umrzeć”. Ta dionizyjska prawda dotyczy zatem nie tylko artystycznego przedstawiania, lecz mówi coś również o ludzkiej kondycji. Wyrażenie zaś w dionizyjski sposób strasznej dionizyjskiej prawdy dalekie musi być od wyważonej harmonii i zdystansowanego umiaru. Jedyne na co może liczyć zapamiętały w szaleńczej trwodze dionizyjski „artysta” to zagubienie się w panteistycznej jedności wszystkich ludzi i przyrody Ale wtedy też różnica pomiędzy dziełem sztuki, artystą a odbiorcą zaniknie, pogrążona w ekstatycznym upodobnieniu. By sztuka stała się możliwa, niezbędna staje się apollińska forma i dający chwilę wytchnienia dystans. Chociaż apollińskość i dionizyjskość mają w intencji Niezschego estetyczne znaczenie, ich ogólnokulturowy sens zidentyfikowano dość szybko. Carl Gustav Jung zarzucał Nietzschemu, że zapomniał on o podstawowym dla Greków religijnym sensie tej antynomii: „Estetyzm jest nowoczesnymi okularami, przez które psychologiczne tajemnice kultu Dionizosa widzi się w takim świetle, w jakim starożytni z pewnością nigdy ich nie widzieli ani nie przeżywali”.
Marek Chojnacki
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 215 - 237
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.012.0588
Fragment
Max Weber i Peter Berger: pytanie o racjonalność religii i o jej miejsce w społeczeństwie
Poweberowska tradycja socjologii religii kryje niewykorzystane dotąd możliwości interpretacji pojęcia sekularyzacji. Możliwości te są na tyle zaskakujące, że mogą skłonić do postawienia pytania, czy użycie tego pojęcia w dotychczasowej refleksji na temat religii i społeczeństwa nie jest w pewnym sensie nieporozumieniem. Dobrym przykładem tego rodzaju reinterpretacji jest artykuł Catherine Colliot-Thélène o odczarowaniu i racjonalizacji u Maxa Webera. Odnosząc się do późnych tekstów Webera na temat socjologii religii, powstałych po książce Etyka protestancka a duch kapitalizmu, twierdzi ona, iż nieuzasadnione jest umieszczanie tych analiz w kontekście interpretacji teorii sekularyzacji. Autorka twierdzi, że ów kontekst, w którym zakłada się że zasadnicza różnica pomiędzy światem nowoczesnym i przednowoczesnym polega na emancypacji spod przemożnego wpływu religii na konstytuowanie się społeczeństwa, nie pasuje do analiz Webera, gdyż zakładają one, iż religia pełni w społeczeństwie kluczową rolę, stanowiąc w nim jedyne źródło sensu. Colliot-Thélène podaje przykład zainspirowanej myślą Webera książki Petera Bergera Święty baldachim, gdzie termin „sekularyzacja” oznacza sytuację, w której religia zostaje wrzucona w rynek komercyjnego współzawodnictwa, pozbawiona właściwej sobie mocy nadawania społeczeństwu powszechnie obowiązujących znaczeń i sensów, przez co społeczeństwo powraca do pierwotnego stanu chaosu i anomii..
Wiktor Marzec
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 239 - 259
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.013.0589
Fragment
Postmarksizm – teoria nieobojętna
Marksizm i jego wszyscy spadkobiercy od teorii krytycznej po postmarksizm to teoria społeczna o praktycznej intencji, ukierunkowana nie tylko na opis i interpretacje, ale i zmianę świata (w myśl osławionej Marksowskiej XI tezy o Feurbachu). Od początku musiał więc stawić czoła aporiom, które „normalna” teoria i filozofia społeczna nierzadko spostrzegały znacznie później. Być może marksizm pod względem ingerencji w opisywaną rzeczywistość nie różni się jakościowo od jakiejkolwiek innej perspektywy, jednakże on od razu czyni to jawnie i oczywiście na zupełnie inną skalę. Kwestia złożonej relacji teorii i praktyki, opisu i rzeczywistości, bytu i powinności, całości i części, faktu i prawdy dotyka prawdopodobnie wszystkich nauk społecznych, w marksizmie uwidaczniając się tylko niepomiernie bardziej wyraziście. Marksizm więc musi być myślany w ścisłej relacji do rzeczywistości, którą opisuje i zmienia, nawet gdy nie urzeczywistnia swoich projektów bezpośrednio w rewolucyjnym czynie. W jakimś sensie jest na nią odpowiedzią, reakcją, próbą jej zmiany, przekształcenia lub chociaż krytycznego zrozumienia. Nie powstaje w próżni,
proklamowany przez wizjonerskiego teoretyka, który wolnym aktem stwarza myśl na wyżynach idealizmu. Jest wynikiem przecięcia czy raczej ciągłego relacyjnego oddziaływania z jednej strony rozwoju myśli („historii idei”), wykształcania się filozoficznych schematów myślenia, nieustannego dialogu z poprzednikami, z drugiej zaś zmian rzeczywistości społecznej, z której wypływa i którą zmienia. Ta relacja do rzeczywistości ma jednak jeszcze jeden, nie mniej ważny, wymiar.
Grażyna Woroniecka
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 7 - 22
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.001.0577
Fragment
Pomysł, że naukowa wiedza o świecie jest konstruktem, narracją, opowieścią budzi odruchowy sprzeciw zaskakująco wielu ludzi. To, co wydaje się oczywiste socjologom wiedzy naukowej: przeświadczenie, iż wiedza jest artefaktem powstającym dzięki zbiorowej, wysoce zinstytucjonalizowanej aktywności ludzi, brzmi często jak herezja także przed uczonymi audytoriami. Sądząc po sile sprzeciwu, jaki zdarza się spotykać, jest to herezja nie jakaś nieistotna, ale taka, która wzburza do głębi, która narusza wręcz fundament wiary w to, że świat jest taki, jakim go widzimy i możemy o nim orzekać coś pewnego. Andrzej Zybertowicz ujmuje to zjawisko opisowo, w kategoriach „przeskoku” między wizjami świata, czy też „kontrintuicyjności” konstruktywistycznego modelu poznania wobec codziennej perspektywy poznawczej (Zybertowicz 1995: 122-123). Niektóre reakcje, choćby kilku moich słuchaczy na studiach doktoranckich z socjologii (sic!) wręcz zaskakiwały emocjonalną siłą kontrataku, do którego czuli się zobligowani odczytując np. tezy Bruna Latoura na temat procedur pracy laboratoryjnej jako osobisty atak na najcenniejsze wartości.
Marcin K. Zwierżdżyński
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 23 - 41
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.002.0578
Fragment
1. Teorie konstruowania w naukach społecznych
Nie ulega wątpliwości, że metaforyka konstruowania na dobre zadomowiła się we współczesnej nauce. W tych kategoriach analizowano już niemal wszystko: od samej rzeczywistości (Berger, Luckmann 1983; Manterys 1997) i nauki (Latour, Woolgar 1979; Amsterdamska 1992), przez tożsamość (Cerulo 1997; Skrendo 2004) i religię (Beckford 2003; Zwierżdżyński 2010), po płeć (Laqueur 1990; Kopciewicz 2007) i problemy społeczne (Schneider 1985; Miś 2008). Teorie konstruowania stosowane są dziś praktycznie w każdej dyscyplinie naukowej, począwszy od antropologii i socjologii (zwłaszcza analizy narratywistyczne i interakcjonistyczne, np. Bruner 1991 i Hałas 2005), psychologii i pedagogiki (np. Gergen 1985 i Klus-Stańska 2000), przez historię i archeologię (np. Gross 1986 i Ostoja-Zagórski 2000), językoznawstwo i literaturoznawstwo (np. Grace 1987 i Kuźma, Skrendo, Madejski 2006), na ekonomii i matematyce kończąc (np. Granovetter 1992 i Piotrowska 2008).
Danuta Chmielewska-Banaszak
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 43 - 63
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.003.0579
Fragment
1. Czym jest konstruktywizm w psychologii?
Konstruktywizm w psychologii nie tworzy spójnej orientacji. Ze względu na wielość teorii i koncepcji, obszerne i zróżnicowane pole badań oraz niejednorodność założeń, bardziej adekwatne wydaje się określenie „konstruktywizmy”. Uporządkowaniu wiedzy dotyczącej teorii i idei konstruktywistycznych w psychologii nie pomaga to, że można i trzeba rozpatrywać je na trzech poziomach: koncepcji dotyczących ogólnej teorii poznania, opisu teoretyczno-empirycznego oraz zastosowań praktycznych, czyli oddziaływań terapeutycznych.
Pierwszy poziom tworzą, między innymi, koncepcje Jeana Piageta, Lwa S. Wygotskiego, George’a Kelly’ego, Jeromy’ego Brunera, Kennetha J. Gergena.
Drugi poziom tworzą, oparte na konstruktywistycznych założeniach teoretyczne i empiryczne opisy funkcjonowania człowieka charakterystyczne dla różnych subdyscyplin psychologii, na przykład psychologii społecznej, psychologii emocji, psychologii osobowości czy teorii komunikacji. Dalsze części artykułu poświęcone są prezentacji konstruktywizmu w psychologii poznawczej, która zdecydowanie dominuje we współczesnej psychologii, a podejście konstruktywistyczne funkcjonuje w jej obrębie jako wiedza podręcznikowa (choć nie jest to dla psychologów poznawczych wiedza oczywista).
Agnieszka Kolasa-Nowak
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 65 - 82
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.004.0580Ewa Bińczyk
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 83 - 100
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.005.0581
Fragment
Prezentowany tu tekst składa się z dwóch części. Pierwsza z nich szkicowo kreśli parametry (właściwie dookreślonej) perspektywy konstruktywistycznej. „Właściwe” dookreślenie polega przy tym na wykorzystaniu określonych zasobów, tj. najnowszych ustaleń studiów nad nauką oraz technologią (częściowo określanych też jako socjologia wiedzy naukowej), a w tym szczególnie teorii aktora-sieci Bruno Latoura i etnografii laboratorium. W obrębie rozwijanej poniżej narracji pozycje konstruktywistyczne konstytuuje zarówno intelektualne przywiązanie do metafory „konstruowania”, jak i konglomerat akceptowanych przesądzeń, z których najważniejsze zostaną wyeksponowane.
Jak pokazuje artykuł, w odniesieniu do najnowszych rozstrzygnięć socjologii wiedzy naukowej oraz studiów nad technologią zasadne wydaje się wprowadzenie etykiety (post)konstruktywizmu. Wybrane racje przemawiające za tym posunięciem interpretacyjnym zostaną wskazane poniżej. Zagadnienie (post)konstruktywizmu w badaniach nad nauką oraz technologią nie będzie tu niestety dyskutowane w sposób pogłębiony. Zostało ono omówione szerzej gdzie indziej (por. Bińczyk 2010).
Michał Bujalski
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 101 - 115
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.006.0582Marcin K. Zwierżdżyński
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 117 - 135
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.007.0583
Fragment
Wiele jest w naukach społecznych pojęć, które można by nazwać paronimami – wystarczająco wiele, by mógł powstać ich słownik. Paronimy to słowa o zbliżonej formie, lecz różnym znaczeniu, podobnie brzmiące, utworzone na tej samej podstawie słowotwórczej, spokrewnione lub niespokrewnione etymologicznie i semantycznie, nazywane najczęściej „wyrazami mylonymi”. Na gruncie nauk społecznych można do nich zaliczyć m.in. takie pary, jak: socjobiologia i biosocjologia, postmodernizm i ponowoczesność, konsumeryzm i konsumpcjonizm, historycyzm i historyzm czy sekularyzm i sekularyzacja. Poza tymi, i wieloma innymi, również konstruktywizm i konstrukcjonizm1, jako pojęcia zdobywające ostatnio coraz więcej zwolenników, zwłaszcza wśród socjologów, psychologów i pedagogów, stosowane są często wymiennie, czasem zupełnie nieświadomie, nierzadko z zadziwiającą wręcz niekonsekwencją. Trudno określić, co decyduje każdorazowo o wyborze określonej etykiety – w grę wchodzić może gust, wygoda, popularność lub po prostu przyzwyczajenie.
Paweł Miech
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 139 - 154
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.008.0584
Fragment
Zły podmiot jest wyzwaniem dla filozofii moralnej. Etyka nie jest w stanie uznać realnej możliwości istnienia podmiotu moralnego, który byłby permanentnie i samoistnie zły. Uznanie tej możliwości wydaje się przeczyć podstawowym elementom definicji podmiotu moralnego, która stwierdza wszakże, że podmiot ten cechuje racjonalność, zdolność do uświadomienia sobie zobowiązań moralnych i wolność, która umożliwia mu poniesienie odpowiedzialności za własne poczynania. Jeśli zgodzimy się, że podmiot moralny jest z zasady świadomy prawa moralnego – musimy uznać, że jest on potencjalnie przynajmniej zdolny działania moralnego. Godząc się na tą logikę dochodzimy do wniosku, iż nawet w dogłębnie zepsutym i zdegenerowanym podmiocie istnieje potencjał do poprawy, istnieje pewien moralnie chwalebny element (np. rozum, wolność, odpowiedzialność). Zło podmiotu jest więc jedynie pewną słabością, niedoskonałością poznania lub działania wynikającą z subiektywnych lub społecznych uwarunkowań.
Przemysław Tacik
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 155 - 171
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.009.0585
Fragment
Deklarując wiarę w zadanie humanistyki w ramach bezwarunkowo otwartego uniwersytetu, Jacques Derrida1 zasugerował przedmiot, który powinien być zadaniem filozoficznej, ale i prawniczej dekonstrukcji: ideę suwerenności państwowej, we wszystkich jej powiązaniach z koncepcją obywatelstwa i praw człowieka. Nigdzie chyba władza nie przekłada się mocniej na kształtowanie definicji człowieczeństwa; nigdzie polityka nie znajduje się bliżej zsekularyzowanej teologii. Pojęcia filozoficzne przeplatają się tam z pojęciami prawnymi, zyskując walor performatywny dzięki działaniu władzy państwowej. Niniejszy artykuł stanowi próbę odpowiedzi na wezwanie, jakie rzuca filozofii idea suwerenności. By mu sprostać, filozofia musi sięgnąć nie tylko do własnych tekstów, lecz również do tekstów prawa, które w odróżnieniu od tych ostatnich – nie muszą zważać na prawdę, mają ją bowiem, wraz z władzą, po swojej stronie.
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 173 - 186
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.010.0586
Fragment
W drugiej dekadzie XXI wieku, w stwierdzeniu, że podmiot jest efektem gier władzy, użycia perswazyjnych form językowych, zabiegów ideologicznych, internalizacji stosunków dominacji etc. nie ma już nic zaskakującego. Jesteśmy dość zblazowani, aby przyjąć taką nowinę z godnością i bez mrugnięcia okiem. Teoria aparatów ideologicznych Louisa Althussera, archeologia wiedzy Michela Foucaulta, a potem rozplenienie się pasożytniczych teorii dyskursu we wszystkich jej odmianach – tej ściśle politycznej w ujęciu rozumu populistycznego Ernesto Laclaua i tej bardziej kognitywistycznej, tj. krytycznej analizy dyskursu, w ujęciu Teuna Adrianusa van Dijka, pozwala nam dziś pojmować podmiot jako zaledwie pozycję lub zbiór pozycji zajętych w sieci dyskursywnej. Mówimy sobie „tak, owszem, jesteśmy zaledwie i tylko miejscem lub zbiorem miejsc w złożonej i wielokrotnie nas przekraczającej sieci relacji znaczeń i relacji sił”. Więcej, bylibyśmy pewnie bardziej zdziwieni, gdyby komuś przyszło do głowy podważyć tę oficjalną doktrynę, której jawną intencją jest zamazanie rozróżnienia na działanie i mówienie, wiedzę o świecie (encyklopedię) oraz wiedzę o języku (leksykon), wreszcie zamazanie dystynkcji, kiedyś świętej, tj. kompetencji i wykonania, oraz – w rezultacie – teorii kompetencji czyli idealnego mówcy/słuchacza oraz teorii wykonania czyli ograniczonego i niejednorodnego językowo, zdeformowanego, spontanicznego, jąkającego się wykonawcy.
Zbigniew Ambrożewicz
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 187 - 213
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.011.0587
Fragment
W Narodzinach tragedii Fryderyk Nietzsche dowodził, ze sztuka teatru zawdzięcza swoje istnienie dwóm żywiołom lub raczej – jak to sam Nietzsche określał – popędom, czyli sposobom artystycznego przedstawiania rzeczywistości: dionizyjskiemu i apolińskiemu. Dionizyjskość to dla Nietzschego muzyczność – ekstatyczna amorficzność; apollińskość, z kolei, to plastyczność, pełna form i kształtów ułuda, wyśniona, by w znośnej dla człowieka postaci ukazać trudną do zniesienia dionizyjską prawdę. Prawdę tę ujawnił królowi Midasowi schwytany przezeń Sylen, towarzysz Dionizosa: „Najlepsze jest dla ciebie zupełnie nieosiągalne: nie narodzić się, nie istnieć, być niczym. Najlepsze zaś po tym jest dla ciebie – prędko umrzeć”. Ta dionizyjska prawda dotyczy zatem nie tylko artystycznego przedstawiania, lecz mówi coś również o ludzkiej kondycji. Wyrażenie zaś w dionizyjski sposób strasznej dionizyjskiej prawdy dalekie musi być od wyważonej harmonii i zdystansowanego umiaru. Jedyne na co może liczyć zapamiętały w szaleńczej trwodze dionizyjski „artysta” to zagubienie się w panteistycznej jedności wszystkich ludzi i przyrody Ale wtedy też różnica pomiędzy dziełem sztuki, artystą a odbiorcą zaniknie, pogrążona w ekstatycznym upodobnieniu. By sztuka stała się możliwa, niezbędna staje się apollińska forma i dający chwilę wytchnienia dystans. Chociaż apollińskość i dionizyjskość mają w intencji Niezschego estetyczne znaczenie, ich ogólnokulturowy sens zidentyfikowano dość szybko. Carl Gustav Jung zarzucał Nietzschemu, że zapomniał on o podstawowym dla Greków religijnym sensie tej antynomii: „Estetyzm jest nowoczesnymi okularami, przez które psychologiczne tajemnice kultu Dionizosa widzi się w takim świetle, w jakim starożytni z pewnością nigdy ich nie widzieli ani nie przeżywali”.
Marek Chojnacki
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 215 - 237
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.012.0588
Fragment
Max Weber i Peter Berger: pytanie o racjonalność religii i o jej miejsce w społeczeństwie
Poweberowska tradycja socjologii religii kryje niewykorzystane dotąd możliwości interpretacji pojęcia sekularyzacji. Możliwości te są na tyle zaskakujące, że mogą skłonić do postawienia pytania, czy użycie tego pojęcia w dotychczasowej refleksji na temat religii i społeczeństwa nie jest w pewnym sensie nieporozumieniem. Dobrym przykładem tego rodzaju reinterpretacji jest artykuł Catherine Colliot-Thélène o odczarowaniu i racjonalizacji u Maxa Webera. Odnosząc się do późnych tekstów Webera na temat socjologii religii, powstałych po książce Etyka protestancka a duch kapitalizmu, twierdzi ona, iż nieuzasadnione jest umieszczanie tych analiz w kontekście interpretacji teorii sekularyzacji. Autorka twierdzi, że ów kontekst, w którym zakłada się że zasadnicza różnica pomiędzy światem nowoczesnym i przednowoczesnym polega na emancypacji spod przemożnego wpływu religii na konstytuowanie się społeczeństwa, nie pasuje do analiz Webera, gdyż zakładają one, iż religia pełni w społeczeństwie kluczową rolę, stanowiąc w nim jedyne źródło sensu. Colliot-Thélène podaje przykład zainspirowanej myślą Webera książki Petera Bergera Święty baldachim, gdzie termin „sekularyzacja” oznacza sytuację, w której religia zostaje wrzucona w rynek komercyjnego współzawodnictwa, pozbawiona właściwej sobie mocy nadawania społeczeństwu powszechnie obowiązujących znaczeń i sensów, przez co społeczeństwo powraca do pierwotnego stanu chaosu i anomii..
Wiktor Marzec
Principia, Vol 56, 2012, pp. 239 - 259
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.013.0589
Fragment
Postmarksizm – teoria nieobojętna
Marksizm i jego wszyscy spadkobiercy od teorii krytycznej po postmarksizm to teoria społeczna o praktycznej intencji, ukierunkowana nie tylko na opis i interpretacje, ale i zmianę świata (w myśl osławionej Marksowskiej XI tezy o Feurbachu). Od początku musiał więc stawić czoła aporiom, które „normalna” teoria i filozofia społeczna nierzadko spostrzegały znacznie później. Być może marksizm pod względem ingerencji w opisywaną rzeczywistość nie różni się jakościowo od jakiejkolwiek innej perspektywy, jednakże on od razu czyni to jawnie i oczywiście na zupełnie inną skalę. Kwestia złożonej relacji teorii i praktyki, opisu i rzeczywistości, bytu i powinności, całości i części, faktu i prawdy dotyka prawdopodobnie wszystkich nauk społecznych, w marksizmie uwidaczniając się tylko niepomiernie bardziej wyraziście. Marksizm więc musi być myślany w ścisłej relacji do rzeczywistości, którą opisuje i zmienia, nawet gdy nie urzeczywistnia swoich projektów bezpośrednio w rewolucyjnym czynie. W jakimś sensie jest na nią odpowiedzią, reakcją, próbą jej zmiany, przekształcenia lub chociaż krytycznego zrozumienia. Nie powstaje w próżni,
proklamowany przez wizjonerskiego teoretyka, który wolnym aktem stwarza myśl na wyżynach idealizmu. Jest wynikiem przecięcia czy raczej ciągłego relacyjnego oddziaływania z jednej strony rozwoju myśli („historii idei”), wykształcania się filozoficznych schematów myślenia, nieustannego dialogu z poprzednikami, z drugiej zaś zmian rzeczywistości społecznej, z której wypływa i którą zmienia. Ta relacja do rzeczywistości ma jednak jeszcze jeden, nie mniej ważny, wymiar.
Publication date: 14.10.2011
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Piotr Augustyniak
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 7 - 24
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.001.0265Karin Wawrzynek, Jadwiga Sebesta
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 25 - 36
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.002.0266Barbara Czardybon
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 37 - 53
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.003.0267Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 55 - 73
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.004.0268W roku 1953 na łamach Philosophische Rundschau pojawił się głośny artykuł Waltera Schulza pt. „Über den philosophiegeschichtlichen Ort Martin Heideggers” („O filozoficzno-dziejowym miejscu Martina Heideggera”). We wstępie tego artykułu jego autor zauważa, że dotychczasowe próby zrozumienia filozofii Heideggera przez pryzmat dziejów oscylowały między dwiema skrajnościami: albo próbowały one ukazać filozofię Heideggera jako coś absolutnie nowego, jako początek „nowego myślenia”, które zostawia za sobą, „przezwycięża” dawną „metafizykę obecności” i „metafizykę podmiotu”, albo też, odwrotnie, próbowały one deprecjonować myśl Heideggera, pokazując, że jest ona w istocie bądź jakąś odmianą znanych z tradycji stanowisk filozoficznych – ot, choćby myśli Kierkegaarda, Hegla czy mistyków niemieckich – bądź też jakimś gatunkiem „metafizyki światła”, „metafizyki źródła” czy „metafizyki refleksji”. W przeciwieństwie do tych prób, których do końca XX wieku pojawiły się dziesiątki najprzeróżniejszych mutacji, proponuje Schulz „pokazać, że filozofia Heideggera wtedy tylko zostanie rzeczowo pojęta, gdy się ją zrozumie dziejowo jako wewnętrzny koniec dziania się zachodniej metafizyki”. Oznacza to, że nie jest ona ani całkowicie wpisana w tradycję, ani całkowicie czymś od niej odciętym
Jerzy Gołosz
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 73 - 97
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.005.0269Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 101 - 106
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.006.0270Tomasz Szubart
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 107 - 132
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.007.0271Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 135 - 175
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.008.0272
Fragment
Z pewnością czasy współczesne sprzyjają poszukiwaniu nowych uzasadnień moralnych, a nawet samych projektów etycznych. Równocześnie poczucie, że refleksja filozoficzna nad sferą etyczną znajduje się w sferze kryzysu nie wydaje się być szczególnie ekscentryczne i zawężone do pewnego tylko rodzaju dyskursów, a liczba „nowych etyk”
dorównuje prawdopodobnie sile tego kryzysu i jest jego najpotężniejszym wyrazem. Wydaje się, że im bardziej niepewni stajemy się naszych wyborów moralnych, tym silniejsza potrzeba budowania nowych, ciągle na nowo uzasadnianych etyk.
Ciekawą krytykę fundamentalizmu zaprezentował John Langshaw Austin, który dominował na filozoficznej scenie Oxfordu w latach pięćdziesiątych ubiegłego wieku. Z uwagi na to, że większość swojego krótkiego życia poświęcił nauczaniu, opublikował tylko kilka artykułów. Tekst Zmysły i przedmioty zmysłowe, na którym, w sporej mierze, opieram interpretację poglądów Austina, został opublikowany po jego śmierci i jest rekonstrukcją notatek filozofa do prowadzonych przez niego wykładów. Austin znany jest w Polsce przede wszystkim jako filozof języka, twórca teorii aktów mowy. Poruszał on jednak także niektóre z kluczowych zagadnień teorii poznania, o czym często się zapomina.
W niniejszej pracy rekonstruuję poglądy Austina, przedstawiając je jako pewną wersję antyfundamentalizmu oraz wskazuję na niektóre wspólne cechy jego koncepcji i teorii eksternalizmu epistemologicznego
Magdalena Wilejczyk
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 177 - 189
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.009.0273
Fragment
Formułowane zazwyczaj interpretacje Etyki nikomachejskiej przyjmują sugerowany przez samego Arystotelesa pogląd, wyraźnie odróżniający człowieka etycznie dzielnego od człowieka zaledwie opanowanego. Opanowanie siebie nie może być według Arystotelesa cnotą, po pierwsze dlatego, że nie istnieje żaden specjalny gatunek uczuć, w odniesieniu do którego byłoby ono środkiem, gdy tymczasem – przypomnijmy – dzielność etyczna jest „trwałą dyspozycją do pewnego rodzaju postanowień, polegającą na zachowywaniu właściwej ze względu na nas średniej miary”, przy czym chodzi tu o średnią miarę właśnie w „doznawaniu namiętności i w postępowaniu”. Drugim powodem uniemożliwiającym utożsamienie człowieka opanowanego z człowiekiem dzielnym jest to, że sama potrzeba bycia opanowanym ujawnia pewien istotny, wewnętrzny niedostatek, polegający mianowicie na rozdwojeniu uczuć oraz kierowanej rozumem woli. Tymczasem człowiek naprawdę prawy, wydaje się twierdzić Arystoteles, nie potrzebuje być opanowany i nie musi już zwyciężać samego siebie, ponieważ stanowi on ściślejszą jedność.
Karolina M. Cern, Bartosz Wojciechowski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 191 - 221
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.010.0274
Fragment
Dwudziestowieczna filozofia obfitowała w burzliwe wydarzenia, zwroty czy też zmiany paradygmatów jej uprawiania, które częstokroć pozostawały pod niewątpliwym wpływem myśli dziewiętnastowiecznej. Można byłoby nawet rzec, iż wyprowadziła radykalne konsekwencje rozważań swych antenatów, czerpiąc z tego właśnie swą wyjątkową. Szczególną rolę w minionym stuleciu zaczęła odgrywać kategoria faktyczności. Stanowi ona swoistą modyfikację pojęcia zmysłowości, któremu przypadło istotne miejsce w filozofii Immanuela Kanta. Odnosiło się ono, ogólnie rzecz biorąc, do relacji czasowych oraz przestrzennych i wraz z pojęciem rozumu oznaczało źródło poznania oraz działania praktycznego.
Olga Dryla
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 223 - 243
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.011.0275
Fragment
Zagadnienie poufności w medycynie była i jest przedmiotem wielu dyskusji; szczególnie interesujące jest pytanie, czy lekarz ma prawo bez zgody pacjenta – lub wręcz przy jego wyraźnym sprzeciwie – udostępniać „osobom trzecim” informacje, które uzyskał w trakcie procesu terapeutycznego. Stosunkowo świeżym wątkiem jest poufność w genetyce klinicznej i konsultacjach genetycznych; tym właśnie problemem mam zamiar zająć się w niniejszym artykule. W artykule można wyróżnić trzy części: na wstępie pokrótce omawiam rolę poufności w etyce medycznej, następnie przechodzę do sposobów uzasadniania zasady poufności, by ostatecznie zająć się dopuszczalnością łamania zasady poufności w genetyce klinicznej.
Dominik Rogóż
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 247 - 266
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.012.0276
Fragment
Współczesna humanistyka karmi się pasją wynajdywania Inności. Inność – z francuskiego alterité, z angielskiego otherness – okazuje się dzisiaj kategorią wszechobecną, która niemal we wszystkich odsłonach ponowoczesności – od filozofii po teologię, od literatury po psychologię, od socjologii po etnologię – odgrywa rolę pierwszoplanową. Postnowoczesność, która krytycznym okiem spogląda na swoje ante, czyli nowoczesność, stanowi w istocie wielką apologię Inności. Nowoczesność bowiem – jak powiedziałby Vincent Descombes, autor głośnej rozprawy L’même et l’autre z 1979 roku – była formacją zdominowaną przez „myślenie tożsamościowe”, przez „mentalność monadologiczną”, przez „świadomość totalizującą”. W obliczu potężnych, metafizycznych systemów karmiących się aspiracją ogarniania całości rzeczywistości, Inność nieuchronnie musiała być marginalizowana, wykluczana poza spójne ramy systemu, „karceryzowana” – by posłużyć się określeniem Michela Foucault’a – bądź też „subordynowana” – by przywołać znany termin Jacques’a Derridy.
Paweł Załęski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 267 - 283
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.013.0277„Odrodzenie” koncepcji społeczeństwa obywatelskiego zwyczajowo kojarzone jest z polityczną opozycją związaną ze związkiem zawodowym „Solidarność”. Swoistym paradoksem zatem jest, że termin ten został wprowadzony do polskiej filozofii niejako avant la lettre w 1949 r. Przez komunistyczny aparat cenzury. Zastąpił on terminy „społeczeństwo mieszczańskie”, „społeczeństwo burżuazyjne” i przede wszystkim najczęściej używany wówczas termin „społeczeństwo cywilne”, stosowany w tłumaczeniach dzieł Marksa zanim Polska znalazła się pod sowieckim protektoratem.
Agnieszka Smrokowska-Reichmann
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 285 - 304
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.014.0278
Przedmiotem czy też podmiotem tego artykułu są masy – Baudrillardowskie neutrum, które stawia opór „imperatywowi racjonalnej komunikacji”. Rok 1978 – rok paryskiego wydania W cieniu milczącej większości – stanowi wyraźną cezurę w twórczości Baudrillarda, tak jeżeli chodzi o główny temat jego rozważań, jak też ich styl. Za ostatnią pracę Baudrillarda spełniającą (choć z trudem) kryteria tradycyjnej naukowej rozprawy o charakterze filozoficzno-socjologicznym przywykło się uważać „Wymianę symboliczną i śmierć” z roku 1976. Baudrillard jasno wyłożył tam swoją teorię symulacji oraz odwołując się do badań etnologicznych i antropologicznych (zwłaszcza Marcela Maussa, ale i Bronisława Malinowskiego), zaproponował logikę wymiany symbolicznej w opozycji do logiki akumulacji. Również wcześniejsze prace Baudrillarda, sprzed roku 1976, uważane są za rozprawy z dziedziny filozofii społecznej / filozofii politycznej / socjologii wyraźnie rozpoznawalne jako takie. Baudrillard zaklasyfikowany został wówczas jako neomarksista, uprawiający, podobnie jak tylu innych neomarksistów, krytykę Marksa.
Piotr Augustyniak
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 7 - 24
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.001.0265Karin Wawrzynek, Jadwiga Sebesta
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 25 - 36
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.002.0266Barbara Czardybon
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 37 - 53
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.003.0267Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 55 - 73
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.004.0268W roku 1953 na łamach Philosophische Rundschau pojawił się głośny artykuł Waltera Schulza pt. „Über den philosophiegeschichtlichen Ort Martin Heideggers” („O filozoficzno-dziejowym miejscu Martina Heideggera”). We wstępie tego artykułu jego autor zauważa, że dotychczasowe próby zrozumienia filozofii Heideggera przez pryzmat dziejów oscylowały między dwiema skrajnościami: albo próbowały one ukazać filozofię Heideggera jako coś absolutnie nowego, jako początek „nowego myślenia”, które zostawia za sobą, „przezwycięża” dawną „metafizykę obecności” i „metafizykę podmiotu”, albo też, odwrotnie, próbowały one deprecjonować myśl Heideggera, pokazując, że jest ona w istocie bądź jakąś odmianą znanych z tradycji stanowisk filozoficznych – ot, choćby myśli Kierkegaarda, Hegla czy mistyków niemieckich – bądź też jakimś gatunkiem „metafizyki światła”, „metafizyki źródła” czy „metafizyki refleksji”. W przeciwieństwie do tych prób, których do końca XX wieku pojawiły się dziesiątki najprzeróżniejszych mutacji, proponuje Schulz „pokazać, że filozofia Heideggera wtedy tylko zostanie rzeczowo pojęta, gdy się ją zrozumie dziejowo jako wewnętrzny koniec dziania się zachodniej metafizyki”. Oznacza to, że nie jest ona ani całkowicie wpisana w tradycję, ani całkowicie czymś od niej odciętym
Jerzy Gołosz
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 73 - 97
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.005.0269Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 101 - 106
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.006.0270Tomasz Szubart
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 107 - 132
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.007.0271Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 135 - 175
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.008.0272
Fragment
Z pewnością czasy współczesne sprzyjają poszukiwaniu nowych uzasadnień moralnych, a nawet samych projektów etycznych. Równocześnie poczucie, że refleksja filozoficzna nad sferą etyczną znajduje się w sferze kryzysu nie wydaje się być szczególnie ekscentryczne i zawężone do pewnego tylko rodzaju dyskursów, a liczba „nowych etyk”
dorównuje prawdopodobnie sile tego kryzysu i jest jego najpotężniejszym wyrazem. Wydaje się, że im bardziej niepewni stajemy się naszych wyborów moralnych, tym silniejsza potrzeba budowania nowych, ciągle na nowo uzasadnianych etyk.
Ciekawą krytykę fundamentalizmu zaprezentował John Langshaw Austin, który dominował na filozoficznej scenie Oxfordu w latach pięćdziesiątych ubiegłego wieku. Z uwagi na to, że większość swojego krótkiego życia poświęcił nauczaniu, opublikował tylko kilka artykułów. Tekst Zmysły i przedmioty zmysłowe, na którym, w sporej mierze, opieram interpretację poglądów Austina, został opublikowany po jego śmierci i jest rekonstrukcją notatek filozofa do prowadzonych przez niego wykładów. Austin znany jest w Polsce przede wszystkim jako filozof języka, twórca teorii aktów mowy. Poruszał on jednak także niektóre z kluczowych zagadnień teorii poznania, o czym często się zapomina.
W niniejszej pracy rekonstruuję poglądy Austina, przedstawiając je jako pewną wersję antyfundamentalizmu oraz wskazuję na niektóre wspólne cechy jego koncepcji i teorii eksternalizmu epistemologicznego
Magdalena Wilejczyk
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 177 - 189
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.009.0273
Fragment
Formułowane zazwyczaj interpretacje Etyki nikomachejskiej przyjmują sugerowany przez samego Arystotelesa pogląd, wyraźnie odróżniający człowieka etycznie dzielnego od człowieka zaledwie opanowanego. Opanowanie siebie nie może być według Arystotelesa cnotą, po pierwsze dlatego, że nie istnieje żaden specjalny gatunek uczuć, w odniesieniu do którego byłoby ono środkiem, gdy tymczasem – przypomnijmy – dzielność etyczna jest „trwałą dyspozycją do pewnego rodzaju postanowień, polegającą na zachowywaniu właściwej ze względu na nas średniej miary”, przy czym chodzi tu o średnią miarę właśnie w „doznawaniu namiętności i w postępowaniu”. Drugim powodem uniemożliwiającym utożsamienie człowieka opanowanego z człowiekiem dzielnym jest to, że sama potrzeba bycia opanowanym ujawnia pewien istotny, wewnętrzny niedostatek, polegający mianowicie na rozdwojeniu uczuć oraz kierowanej rozumem woli. Tymczasem człowiek naprawdę prawy, wydaje się twierdzić Arystoteles, nie potrzebuje być opanowany i nie musi już zwyciężać samego siebie, ponieważ stanowi on ściślejszą jedność.
Karolina M. Cern, Bartosz Wojciechowski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 191 - 221
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.010.0274
Fragment
Dwudziestowieczna filozofia obfitowała w burzliwe wydarzenia, zwroty czy też zmiany paradygmatów jej uprawiania, które częstokroć pozostawały pod niewątpliwym wpływem myśli dziewiętnastowiecznej. Można byłoby nawet rzec, iż wyprowadziła radykalne konsekwencje rozważań swych antenatów, czerpiąc z tego właśnie swą wyjątkową. Szczególną rolę w minionym stuleciu zaczęła odgrywać kategoria faktyczności. Stanowi ona swoistą modyfikację pojęcia zmysłowości, któremu przypadło istotne miejsce w filozofii Immanuela Kanta. Odnosiło się ono, ogólnie rzecz biorąc, do relacji czasowych oraz przestrzennych i wraz z pojęciem rozumu oznaczało źródło poznania oraz działania praktycznego.
Olga Dryla
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 223 - 243
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.011.0275
Fragment
Zagadnienie poufności w medycynie była i jest przedmiotem wielu dyskusji; szczególnie interesujące jest pytanie, czy lekarz ma prawo bez zgody pacjenta – lub wręcz przy jego wyraźnym sprzeciwie – udostępniać „osobom trzecim” informacje, które uzyskał w trakcie procesu terapeutycznego. Stosunkowo świeżym wątkiem jest poufność w genetyce klinicznej i konsultacjach genetycznych; tym właśnie problemem mam zamiar zająć się w niniejszym artykule. W artykule można wyróżnić trzy części: na wstępie pokrótce omawiam rolę poufności w etyce medycznej, następnie przechodzę do sposobów uzasadniania zasady poufności, by ostatecznie zająć się dopuszczalnością łamania zasady poufności w genetyce klinicznej.
Dominik Rogóż
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 247 - 266
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.012.0276
Fragment
Współczesna humanistyka karmi się pasją wynajdywania Inności. Inność – z francuskiego alterité, z angielskiego otherness – okazuje się dzisiaj kategorią wszechobecną, która niemal we wszystkich odsłonach ponowoczesności – od filozofii po teologię, od literatury po psychologię, od socjologii po etnologię – odgrywa rolę pierwszoplanową. Postnowoczesność, która krytycznym okiem spogląda na swoje ante, czyli nowoczesność, stanowi w istocie wielką apologię Inności. Nowoczesność bowiem – jak powiedziałby Vincent Descombes, autor głośnej rozprawy L’même et l’autre z 1979 roku – była formacją zdominowaną przez „myślenie tożsamościowe”, przez „mentalność monadologiczną”, przez „świadomość totalizującą”. W obliczu potężnych, metafizycznych systemów karmiących się aspiracją ogarniania całości rzeczywistości, Inność nieuchronnie musiała być marginalizowana, wykluczana poza spójne ramy systemu, „karceryzowana” – by posłużyć się określeniem Michela Foucault’a – bądź też „subordynowana” – by przywołać znany termin Jacques’a Derridy.
Paweł Załęski
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 267 - 283
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.013.0277„Odrodzenie” koncepcji społeczeństwa obywatelskiego zwyczajowo kojarzone jest z polityczną opozycją związaną ze związkiem zawodowym „Solidarność”. Swoistym paradoksem zatem jest, że termin ten został wprowadzony do polskiej filozofii niejako avant la lettre w 1949 r. Przez komunistyczny aparat cenzury. Zastąpił on terminy „społeczeństwo mieszczańskie”, „społeczeństwo burżuazyjne” i przede wszystkim najczęściej używany wówczas termin „społeczeństwo cywilne”, stosowany w tłumaczeniach dzieł Marksa zanim Polska znalazła się pod sowieckim protektoratem.
Agnieszka Smrokowska-Reichmann
Principia, Vol. 54-55, 2011, pp. 285 - 304
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843887PI.11.014.0278
Przedmiotem czy też podmiotem tego artykułu są masy – Baudrillardowskie neutrum, które stawia opór „imperatywowi racjonalnej komunikacji”. Rok 1978 – rok paryskiego wydania W cieniu milczącej większości – stanowi wyraźną cezurę w twórczości Baudrillarda, tak jeżeli chodzi o główny temat jego rozważań, jak też ich styl. Za ostatnią pracę Baudrillarda spełniającą (choć z trudem) kryteria tradycyjnej naukowej rozprawy o charakterze filozoficzno-socjologicznym przywykło się uważać „Wymianę symboliczną i śmierć” z roku 1976. Baudrillard jasno wyłożył tam swoją teorię symulacji oraz odwołując się do badań etnologicznych i antropologicznych (zwłaszcza Marcela Maussa, ale i Bronisława Malinowskiego), zaproponował logikę wymiany symbolicznej w opozycji do logiki akumulacji. Również wcześniejsze prace Baudrillarda, sprzed roku 1976, uważane są za rozprawy z dziedziny filozofii społecznej / filozofii politycznej / socjologii wyraźnie rozpoznawalne jako takie. Baudrillard zaklasyfikowany został wówczas jako neomarksista, uprawiający, podobnie jak tylu innych neomarksistów, krytykę Marksa.
Publication date: 14.10.2010
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Andrzej Nowakowski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 7 - 30
Fragment
Czy coś istnieje? Tak, oczywiście; samo zadanie tego pytania powinno być sprawą wstydliwą dla pytającego – zalicza go przecież w poczet głupców. Nikt na serio go nie zadaje ani nie zadawał, ani w życiu codziennym, ani nawet w najbardziej ekstrawaganckich rozważaniach filozoficznych. Jeden Gorgiasz twierdził (chociaż nie pytał, czy), że nic nie istnieje, lecz to był zapewne żart wielkiego retora, cyrkowa sztuczka ku uciesze publiczności.
Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 31 - 48
Fragment
Praca niniejsza poświęcona jest Davidsonowskiej teorii interpretacji. Jesteśmy jednak przekonani, że prezentacja dowolnego zagadnienia, w tym również zagadnienia z zakresu historii filozofii, staje się głębsza i bardziej wyrazista, gdy ma charakter dialektyczny. Artykuł ten pomyślany jest tak, by stale towarzyszył nam adwersarz. Obok własnego wywodu będziemy przytaczać i zbijać jego tezy. Ponieważ zaś wierzymy w przewagę sporu rzeczywistego nad fikcyjnym, będzie on osobą rzeczywistą (niech nam to wybaczy). Wybitnym przedstawicielem błądzących w naszej opinii interpretatorów Davidsona jest Jerzy Kmita. Jego książka Jak słowa łączą się ze światem [13] wydana już ponad 10 lat temu wciąż pozostaje na polskim rynku, choć traktuje też o innych autorach, najpełniejszym opracowaniem prac naszego bohatera. Trzeba też przyznać, że znajduje niewielką konkurencję wliteraturze światowej. W kilku miejscach zostanie wspomniany także Richard Rorty.
Tomasz Zarębski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 49 - 66
Fragment
Wedle powszechnej i chyba niepodważalnej dziś opinii Ludwig Wittgenstein należy do nielicznego grona tych filozofów, którzy wywarli największy wpływ na kształt filozofii dwudziestego wieku – zwłaszcza filozofii języka; wpływ ten z pewnością trwa zresztą nadal. W przypadku autora Dociekań filozoficznych panuje jednak niemal równie powszechny brak zgody co do tego, jakie stanowisko filozoficzne rzeczywiście zajmował i jakie konsekwencje można z niego wyprowadzić.
Jadwiga Wiertlewska-Bielarz
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 67 - 84
Fragment
W tekście tym proponuję interpretację tezy głoszącej, że znaczeniem wyrażenia językowego jest jego użycie. Teza ta nie tylko jest wynikiem krytyki podjętej przez Wittgensteina w Dociekaniach swych wcześniejszych poglądów, ale także konsekwencją nowego podejścia do języka
Marek Rakoczy
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 85 - 101
Fragment
Zarówno w Traktacie, jak w późniejszych rozważaniach, Wittgenstein uznał sceptycyzm kartezjański – kwestionujący prawomocność wszelkich zdań dotyczących świata zewnętrznego – za niedorzeczność, którą należy, wraz z większością problemów epistemologii nowożytnej, oddalić. A jednak wskazanie na niemożność przedstawienia racji, jakiej żąda sceptyk, może sugerować fiasko Wittgensteinowskiego przedsięwzięcia: jeśli przedsięwzięcie to raczej otwiera, niŜ zamyka drogę sceptycyzmowi, to intencje za nim stojące – zdaniem niektórych – stają się kwestią sporną. W artykule tym przyjmuje, że antysceptycyzm Wittgensteina nie podlega dyskusji. Dyskusji podlega jedynie fakt, czy zostaje on przekonująco sformułowany.
Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 105 - 111
Fragment
Wciąż brak nam dobrej teorii obowiązku. Powody tego stanu rzeczy są rozliczne. Głównym jest zapewne ten, że intencje większości badaczy nie są neutralne aksjologicznie, czyli budując teorię starają się oni wspierać określone stanowiska normatywne, a wzbraniają przed rozważaniem rozwiązań teoretycznych, o których można by sądzić, że uzasadniają stanowiska etycznie im wrogie. Nie może się jednak rozwijać nauka, gdy spętana jest przekonaniami moralnymi, religijnymi, ideologicznymi czy światopoglądowymi.
Tomasz Grzegorek
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 113 - 131
Fragment
Spór między internalizmem i eksternalizmem w filozofii moralności dotyczy tego, czy analiza sądu moralnego (np. „Jan powinien oddać dług”) wymaga uwzględnienia motywacji podmiotu do odpowiedniego postępowania. Internalizm jest stanowiskiem stwierdzającym konieczność takiego uwzględnienia, eksternalizm przeciwnie – postuluje analizę sądu moralnego bez odwołania do motywów. Spór ten można również opisać na płaszczyźnie innej niż logiczna mianowicie, jak ją nazywa Stephen Darwall, „egzystencjalnej”.
Maria Zowisło
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 133 - 155
Fragment
Zagadnienie trwałości i zmiany, posiadające swoją ustaloną pozycję itradycję w ramach socjologii jest także istotnym problemem estetyki współczesnej, która rozważa je pod postacią pytania o jedność (ciągłość) czy też ostateczny rozbrat (zerwanie) sztuki współczesnej ze sztuką klasyczną.
Krzysztof Wąchal
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 157 - 175
Fragment
Przedmiotem antropologii kulturowej jest oczywiście kultura. „Problem polega na tym, że nikt nie jest całkiem pewien, co to jest kultura. Pojęcie to [...] jest ulotne, niestałe, encyklopedyczne i normatywnie nacechowane”. Nic więc dziwnego, iż bywa kwestionowane; z wielu stron słychać głosy, iż należałoby zeń zrezygnować dla dobra nauki czy nawet ludzkości. W definiowaniu przedmiotu swoich badań antropologowie obchodzą się z niesłychaną nonszalancją. Dla przykładu: C.Geertz w Zastanym świetle przywołuje Kluckhohna i Kroebera, którym udało się skatalogować aż 171 definicji tego pojęcia.
Lotar Rasiński
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 177 - 192
Fragment
Prezentowany artykuł jest efektem rozważań, jakie przeprowadziłem w swojej dysertacji doktorskiej, zatytułowanej Hegemonia i społeczeństwo. Analiza i rekonstrukcja dyskursywnej teorii władzy. Zbyt długi namysł nad formą publikacji całości dysertacji – co doprowadziło do dezauktualizacji pewnych jej fragmentów – skłonił mnie ostatecznie do publikacji czegoś w rodzaju „rekapitulacji”, która zaprezentuje jej, moim zdaniem, najważniejsze rezultaty
Xymena Synak-Pskit
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 191 - 203
Fragment
Podejmując próbę określenia koncepcji semantycznej zarysowanej w filozofii Derridy narażam się być może na głosy sprzeciwu wobec możliwości mówienia o jakiejkolwiek systematyczności dyskursu proponowanego przez myśl dekonstrukcyjną. Myślę jednak, że obecny stan refleksji filozoficznej spłaszcza poniekąd filozofię derridiańską, redukując ją do anty-systemu, interpretacyjnego chaosu czy też filozoficznego kuglarstwa, podczas gdy stanowi ona pole dla szerokiej interpretacji, wcale nie o charakterze „wszystkoizmu”.
Marzenna Cyzman
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 203 - 215
Fragment
Pomysł zaprezentowania i krytycznej analizy koncepcji nazw własnych sformułowanej Romana Ingardena wynika z konieczności uzupełnienia swoistej luki w pracach na temat jego ontologii, estetyki czy teorii dzieła literackiego. Refleksja o nazwach własnych pojawia się w nich bowiem nader rzadko, najczęściej w kontekście rozważań głównych, dla których stanowi jedynie przyczynek, uzupełnienie czy dygresję.
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 217 - 237
Fragment
W dniu 7 V 1900 roku, na posiedzeniu działającego w Wiedniu Towarzystwa Filozoficznego, Maurycy Straszewski (1848-1921) wygłosił wykład pt. Ideen zur Philosphie der Geschichte der Philosophie, którego tekst wydał później w języku polskim, jednak już pod zmienionym tytułem: Pomysł do ujęcia dziejów filozofii w całości. W pierwszych partiach swego wystąpienia, dokonując wstępnej ekspozycji tematu, odwołał się Straszewski do osobliwego wydarzenia, na które raczej nie zwracano w tym czasie uwagi. Chodziło o prawdopodobną rocznicę publicznego ogłoszenia przez Talesa poglądów na temat genezy i natury rzeczywistości, co miało – jego zdaniem – dokonać się około 600 roku p.n.e. i stanowić zarazem początek filozofii. W pełnych patosu słowach mówił dalej o niezerwanej już nigdy później nici tradycji filozoficznego myślenia, o duchowym szlachectwie wszystkich filozofujących, które nie tylko przysparza im i ich dyscyplinie dostojeństwa, lecz które nade wszystko pociąga za sobą określone obowiązki.
Andrzej Nowakowski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 7 - 30
Fragment
Czy coś istnieje? Tak, oczywiście; samo zadanie tego pytania powinno być sprawą wstydliwą dla pytającego – zalicza go przecież w poczet głupców. Nikt na serio go nie zadaje ani nie zadawał, ani w życiu codziennym, ani nawet w najbardziej ekstrawaganckich rozważaniach filozoficznych. Jeden Gorgiasz twierdził (chociaż nie pytał, czy), że nic nie istnieje, lecz to był zapewne żart wielkiego retora, cyrkowa sztuczka ku uciesze publiczności.
Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 31 - 48
Fragment
Praca niniejsza poświęcona jest Davidsonowskiej teorii interpretacji. Jesteśmy jednak przekonani, że prezentacja dowolnego zagadnienia, w tym również zagadnienia z zakresu historii filozofii, staje się głębsza i bardziej wyrazista, gdy ma charakter dialektyczny. Artykuł ten pomyślany jest tak, by stale towarzyszył nam adwersarz. Obok własnego wywodu będziemy przytaczać i zbijać jego tezy. Ponieważ zaś wierzymy w przewagę sporu rzeczywistego nad fikcyjnym, będzie on osobą rzeczywistą (niech nam to wybaczy). Wybitnym przedstawicielem błądzących w naszej opinii interpretatorów Davidsona jest Jerzy Kmita. Jego książka Jak słowa łączą się ze światem [13] wydana już ponad 10 lat temu wciąż pozostaje na polskim rynku, choć traktuje też o innych autorach, najpełniejszym opracowaniem prac naszego bohatera. Trzeba też przyznać, że znajduje niewielką konkurencję wliteraturze światowej. W kilku miejscach zostanie wspomniany także Richard Rorty.
Tomasz Zarębski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 49 - 66
Fragment
Wedle powszechnej i chyba niepodważalnej dziś opinii Ludwig Wittgenstein należy do nielicznego grona tych filozofów, którzy wywarli największy wpływ na kształt filozofii dwudziestego wieku – zwłaszcza filozofii języka; wpływ ten z pewnością trwa zresztą nadal. W przypadku autora Dociekań filozoficznych panuje jednak niemal równie powszechny brak zgody co do tego, jakie stanowisko filozoficzne rzeczywiście zajmował i jakie konsekwencje można z niego wyprowadzić.
Jadwiga Wiertlewska-Bielarz
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 67 - 84
Fragment
W tekście tym proponuję interpretację tezy głoszącej, że znaczeniem wyrażenia językowego jest jego użycie. Teza ta nie tylko jest wynikiem krytyki podjętej przez Wittgensteina w Dociekaniach swych wcześniejszych poglądów, ale także konsekwencją nowego podejścia do języka
Marek Rakoczy
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 85 - 101
Fragment
Zarówno w Traktacie, jak w późniejszych rozważaniach, Wittgenstein uznał sceptycyzm kartezjański – kwestionujący prawomocność wszelkich zdań dotyczących świata zewnętrznego – za niedorzeczność, którą należy, wraz z większością problemów epistemologii nowożytnej, oddalić. A jednak wskazanie na niemożność przedstawienia racji, jakiej żąda sceptyk, może sugerować fiasko Wittgensteinowskiego przedsięwzięcia: jeśli przedsięwzięcie to raczej otwiera, niŜ zamyka drogę sceptycyzmowi, to intencje za nim stojące – zdaniem niektórych – stają się kwestią sporną. W artykule tym przyjmuje, że antysceptycyzm Wittgensteina nie podlega dyskusji. Dyskusji podlega jedynie fakt, czy zostaje on przekonująco sformułowany.
Roman Godlewski
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 105 - 111
Fragment
Wciąż brak nam dobrej teorii obowiązku. Powody tego stanu rzeczy są rozliczne. Głównym jest zapewne ten, że intencje większości badaczy nie są neutralne aksjologicznie, czyli budując teorię starają się oni wspierać określone stanowiska normatywne, a wzbraniają przed rozważaniem rozwiązań teoretycznych, o których można by sądzić, że uzasadniają stanowiska etycznie im wrogie. Nie może się jednak rozwijać nauka, gdy spętana jest przekonaniami moralnymi, religijnymi, ideologicznymi czy światopoglądowymi.
Tomasz Grzegorek
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 113 - 131
Fragment
Spór między internalizmem i eksternalizmem w filozofii moralności dotyczy tego, czy analiza sądu moralnego (np. „Jan powinien oddać dług”) wymaga uwzględnienia motywacji podmiotu do odpowiedniego postępowania. Internalizm jest stanowiskiem stwierdzającym konieczność takiego uwzględnienia, eksternalizm przeciwnie – postuluje analizę sądu moralnego bez odwołania do motywów. Spór ten można również opisać na płaszczyźnie innej niż logiczna mianowicie, jak ją nazywa Stephen Darwall, „egzystencjalnej”.
Maria Zowisło
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 133 - 155
Fragment
Zagadnienie trwałości i zmiany, posiadające swoją ustaloną pozycję itradycję w ramach socjologii jest także istotnym problemem estetyki współczesnej, która rozważa je pod postacią pytania o jedność (ciągłość) czy też ostateczny rozbrat (zerwanie) sztuki współczesnej ze sztuką klasyczną.
Krzysztof Wąchal
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 157 - 175
Fragment
Przedmiotem antropologii kulturowej jest oczywiście kultura. „Problem polega na tym, że nikt nie jest całkiem pewien, co to jest kultura. Pojęcie to [...] jest ulotne, niestałe, encyklopedyczne i normatywnie nacechowane”. Nic więc dziwnego, iż bywa kwestionowane; z wielu stron słychać głosy, iż należałoby zeń zrezygnować dla dobra nauki czy nawet ludzkości. W definiowaniu przedmiotu swoich badań antropologowie obchodzą się z niesłychaną nonszalancją. Dla przykładu: C.Geertz w Zastanym świetle przywołuje Kluckhohna i Kroebera, którym udało się skatalogować aż 171 definicji tego pojęcia.
Lotar Rasiński
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 177 - 192
Fragment
Prezentowany artykuł jest efektem rozważań, jakie przeprowadziłem w swojej dysertacji doktorskiej, zatytułowanej Hegemonia i społeczeństwo. Analiza i rekonstrukcja dyskursywnej teorii władzy. Zbyt długi namysł nad formą publikacji całości dysertacji – co doprowadziło do dezauktualizacji pewnych jej fragmentów – skłonił mnie ostatecznie do publikacji czegoś w rodzaju „rekapitulacji”, która zaprezentuje jej, moim zdaniem, najważniejsze rezultaty
Xymena Synak-Pskit
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 191 - 203
Fragment
Podejmując próbę określenia koncepcji semantycznej zarysowanej w filozofii Derridy narażam się być może na głosy sprzeciwu wobec możliwości mówienia o jakiejkolwiek systematyczności dyskursu proponowanego przez myśl dekonstrukcyjną. Myślę jednak, że obecny stan refleksji filozoficznej spłaszcza poniekąd filozofię derridiańską, redukując ją do anty-systemu, interpretacyjnego chaosu czy też filozoficznego kuglarstwa, podczas gdy stanowi ona pole dla szerokiej interpretacji, wcale nie o charakterze „wszystkoizmu”.
Marzenna Cyzman
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 203 - 215
Fragment
Pomysł zaprezentowania i krytycznej analizy koncepcji nazw własnych sformułowanej Romana Ingardena wynika z konieczności uzupełnienia swoistej luki w pracach na temat jego ontologii, estetyki czy teorii dzieła literackiego. Refleksja o nazwach własnych pojawia się w nich bowiem nader rzadko, najczęściej w kontekście rozważań głównych, dla których stanowi jedynie przyczynek, uzupełnienie czy dygresję.
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Vol 53, 2010, pp. 217 - 237
Fragment
W dniu 7 V 1900 roku, na posiedzeniu działającego w Wiedniu Towarzystwa Filozoficznego, Maurycy Straszewski (1848-1921) wygłosił wykład pt. Ideen zur Philosphie der Geschichte der Philosophie, którego tekst wydał później w języku polskim, jednak już pod zmienionym tytułem: Pomysł do ujęcia dziejów filozofii w całości. W pierwszych partiach swego wystąpienia, dokonując wstępnej ekspozycji tematu, odwołał się Straszewski do osobliwego wydarzenia, na które raczej nie zwracano w tym czasie uwagi. Chodziło o prawdopodobną rocznicę publicznego ogłoszenia przez Talesa poglądów na temat genezy i natury rzeczywistości, co miało – jego zdaniem – dokonać się około 600 roku p.n.e. i stanowić zarazem początek filozofii. W pełnych patosu słowach mówił dalej o niezerwanej już nigdy później nici tradycji filozoficznego myślenia, o duchowym szlachectwie wszystkich filozofujących, które nie tylko przysparza im i ich dyscyplinie dostojeństwa, lecz które nade wszystko pociąga za sobą określone obowiązki.
Publication date: 2009
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editor: Katarzyna Guczalska
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 11 - 31
Sławomir Szymański
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 43 - 60
Paweł Sikora
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 61 - 75
Mirosław Żelazny
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 113 - 120
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 143 - 161
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 163 - 182
Aneta Rostkowska
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 185 - 199
Mariusz Ferenc
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 201 - 210
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 11 - 31
Sławomir Szymański
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 43 - 60
Paweł Sikora
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 61 - 75
Mirosław Żelazny
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 113 - 120
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 143 - 161
Ewa Nowak
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 163 - 182
Aneta Rostkowska
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 185 - 199
Mariusz Ferenc
Principia, Vol 51-52, 2009, pp. 201 - 210
Publication date: 03.01.2008
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 9 - 38
Janusz Mizera
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 71 - 90
Sławomir Stasikowski
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 101 - 110
Aleksandra Derra
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 145 - 164
Marek Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 165 - 184
Michał Kruszelnicki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 187 - 220
Marta Szabat
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 245 - 266
Agnieszka Smrokowska-Reichmann
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 267 - 282
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 9 - 38
Janusz Mizera
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 71 - 90
Sławomir Stasikowski
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 101 - 110
Aleksandra Derra
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 145 - 164
Marek Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 165 - 184
Michał Kruszelnicki
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 187 - 220
Marta Szabat
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 245 - 266
Agnieszka Smrokowska-Reichmann
Principia, Volume 50, 2008, pp. 267 - 282
Publication date: 03.01.2008
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Piotr Nowara
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 21 - 36
Marek Łagosz
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 37 - 62
Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 63 - 90
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 91 - 123
Cezary Woźniak
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 125 - 138
Waldemar Bulira
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 139 - 154
Rafał Włodarczyk
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 155 - 172
Paweł Bankiewicz
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 173 - 190
Łukasz Kołoczek
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 191 - 205
Katarzyna Filutowska
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 207 - 212
Jacek Kołtan
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 213 - 217
Paweł Czarnecki
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 218 - 220
Piotr Nowara
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 21 - 36
Marek Łagosz
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 37 - 62
Daniel Roland Sobota
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 63 - 90
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 91 - 123
Cezary Woźniak
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 125 - 138
Waldemar Bulira
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 139 - 154
Rafał Włodarczyk
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 155 - 172
Paweł Bankiewicz
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 173 - 190
Łukasz Kołoczek
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 191 - 205
Katarzyna Filutowska
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 207 - 212
Jacek Kołtan
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 213 - 217
Paweł Czarnecki
Principia, Volume 49, 2007, pp. 218 - 220
Publication date: 03.12.2007
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editor: Marcin Waligóra
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 17 - 32
Stanisław Judycki
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 33 - 52
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 53 - 77
Małgorzata Bogaczyk
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 95 - 112
Marek Maciejczak
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 123 - 142
Jan Woleński
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 148 - 158
Paweł Dybel
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 159 - 178
Janusz Mizera
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 179 - 210
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 229 - 246
Andrzej Leder
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 247 - 266
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 267 - 280
Katarzyna Barska
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 281 - 293
Przemysław Białek
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 295 - 306
Jan Piasecki
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 335 - 341
Tomasz Komendziński
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 342 - 347
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 349 - 351
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 17 - 32
Stanisław Judycki
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 33 - 52
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 53 - 77
Małgorzata Bogaczyk
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 95 - 112
Marek Maciejczak
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 123 - 142
Jan Woleński
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 148 - 158
Paweł Dybel
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 159 - 178
Janusz Mizera
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 179 - 210
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 229 - 246
Andrzej Leder
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 247 - 266
Tomasz Bekrycht
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 267 - 280
Katarzyna Barska
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 281 - 293
Przemysław Białek
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 295 - 306
Jan Piasecki
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 335 - 341
Tomasz Komendziński
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 342 - 347
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 47-48, 2007, pp. 349 - 351
Publication date: 03.12.2007
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editor: Janusz Goćkowski
Krzysztof Kiciński
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 5 - 13
Janusz Mariański
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 15 - 42
Mirosław Chałubiński
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 43 - 56
Katarzyna M. Machowska
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 57 - 80
Barbara Chyrowicz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 81 - 92
Ryszard Kleszcz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 93 - 108
Joanna Dudek
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 109 - 128
Magdałena Lejzerowicz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 129 - 140
Krzysztof Sztalt
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 141 - 149
Janusz Goćkowski, Anna Woźniak
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 151 - 170
Grażyna Woroniecka
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 171 - 186
Przemysław Kisiel
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 187 - 198
Paweł Woroniecki
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 209 - 224
Agnieszka Klarman
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 225 - 244
Beata Błaszczyk
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 245 - 257
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 259 - 264
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 265 - 272
Krzysztof Kiciński
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 5 - 13
Janusz Mariański
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 15 - 42
Mirosław Chałubiński
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 43 - 56
Katarzyna M. Machowska
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 57 - 80
Barbara Chyrowicz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 81 - 92
Ryszard Kleszcz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 93 - 108
Joanna Dudek
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 109 - 128
Magdałena Lejzerowicz
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 129 - 140
Krzysztof Sztalt
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 141 - 149
Janusz Goćkowski, Anna Woźniak
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 151 - 170
Grażyna Woroniecka
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 171 - 186
Przemysław Kisiel
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 187 - 198
Paweł Woroniecki
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 209 - 224
Agnieszka Klarman
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 225 - 244
Beata Błaszczyk
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 245 - 257
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 259 - 264
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Volume 45-46, 2006, pp. 265 - 272
Publication date: 01.05.2005
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Ernest Gellner
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 5 - 21
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 23 - 41
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 43 - 79
Tomasz Sahaj
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 81 - 91
Mateusz W. Oleksy
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 105 - 120
Anna Głąb
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 121 - 150
Andrzej Lorenz
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 151 - 167
Krzysztof Guczalski
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 169 - 199
Aaron Ridley
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 201 - 218
Radosław Kuliniak, Tomasz Małyszek
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 221 - 226
Paweł Sikora
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 231 - 246
Jacek Uglik
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 247 - 258
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 261 - 272
Agata Mergler
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 273 - 277
Karolina Wigura, Jarosław Kuisz
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 278 - 291
Ludmiła Olszewska
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 292 - 300
Zuzanna Adam
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 301 - 303
Ernest Gellner
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 5 - 21
Szymon Wróbel
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 23 - 41
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 43 - 79
Tomasz Sahaj
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 81 - 91
Mateusz W. Oleksy
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 105 - 120
Anna Głąb
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 121 - 150
Andrzej Lorenz
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 151 - 167
Krzysztof Guczalski
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 169 - 199
Aaron Ridley
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 201 - 218
Radosław Kuliniak, Tomasz Małyszek
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 221 - 226
Paweł Sikora
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 231 - 246
Jacek Uglik
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 247 - 258
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 261 - 272
Agata Mergler
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 273 - 277
Karolina Wigura, Jarosław Kuisz
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 278 - 291
Ludmiła Olszewska
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 292 - 300
Zuzanna Adam
Principia, Volume 43-44, 2006, pp. 301 - 303
Publication date: 2005
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 31 - 56
Artur Pacewicz
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 57 - 76
Olga Dryla
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 77 - 96
Anna Tomaszewska
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 99 - 122
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 185 - 209
Monika Bobako
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 211 - 231
Wioletta Kazimierska-Jeżyk
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 261 - 277
Andrzej Leder
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 279 - 285
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 287 - 291
Andrzej Dąbrowski
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 293 - 299
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 301 - 307
Aneta Rostkowska
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 308 - 313
Justyna Oziewicz
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 314 - 322
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 31 - 56
Artur Pacewicz
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 57 - 76
Olga Dryla
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 77 - 96
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 185 - 209
Monika Bobako
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 211 - 231
Wioletta Kazimierska-Jeżyk
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 261 - 277
Andrzej Leder
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 279 - 285
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 287 - 291
Andrzej Dąbrowski
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 293 - 299
Jerzy Pawliszcze
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 301 - 307
Aneta Rostkowska
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 308 - 313
Justyna Oziewicz
Principia, Volume 41-42, 2005, pp. 314 - 322
Publication date: 2004
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Publication date: 2004
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Sławomir Szymański
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 17 - 32
Agata Bielik-Robson
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 33 - 64
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 85 - 98
Amedeo G. Conte
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 101 - 114
Katarzyna M. Machowska
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 169 - 188
Przemysław Kisiel
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 205 - 217
Alicja Głutkowska
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 219 - 224
Tomasz Łysak
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 225 - 232
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 233 - 238
Sławomir Szymański
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 17 - 32
Agata Bielik-Robson
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 33 - 64
Mirosław Tyl
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 85 - 98
Amedeo G. Conte
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 101 - 114
Katarzyna M. Machowska
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 169 - 188
Przemysław Kisiel
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 205 - 217
Alicja Głutkowska
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 219 - 224
Tomasz Łysak
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 225 - 232
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 39, 2004, pp. 233 - 238
Publication date: 2004
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Redakcja tomu: Piotr Juchacz
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 45 - 60
Manuel Jiménez Redondo
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 63 - 85
Martin Bondeli
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 105 - 123
Wolfgang Kersting
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 127 - 142
Marion Heinz
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 161 - 173
Ewa Czerwińska
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 175 - 194
Piotr W. Juchacz
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 195 - 203
Jerzy Kmita
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 207 - 220
Anna Pałubicka
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 233 - 254
Jarosław Boruszewski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 255 - 273
Karolina M. Cern
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 313 - 331
Jan Such
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 333 - 337
Anna Jamroziakowa
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 339 - 352
Michał Garsztka
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 366 - 374
Karolina M. Cern
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 375 - 382
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 383 - 392
Tomasz Zarębski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 393 - 396
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 397 - 400
Manuel Jiménez Redondo
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 63 - 85
Martin Bondeli
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 105 - 123
Wolfgang Kersting
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 127 - 142
Marion Heinz
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 161 - 173
Ewa Czerwińska
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 175 - 194
Piotr W. Juchacz
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 195 - 203
Jerzy Kmita
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 207 - 220
Anna Pałubicka
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 233 - 254
Jarosław Boruszewski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 255 - 273
Karolina M. Cern
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 313 - 331
Jan Such
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 333 - 337
Anna Jamroziakowa
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 339 - 352
Michał Garsztka
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 366 - 374
Karolina M. Cern
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 375 - 382
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 383 - 392
Tomasz Zarębski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 393 - 396
Andrzej Przyłębski
Principia, Volume 37-38, 2004, pp. 397 - 400
Publication date: 2003
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Immanuel Kant
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 5 - 22
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 39 - 56
Lino J. German
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 57 - 72
Józef Gołuchowski
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 93 - 122
Stefan Zabieglik
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 123 - 149
Andrzej Leśniak
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 163 - 180
Niels Nymann Eriksen
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 193 - 208
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 225 - 238
Katarzyna Barska
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 239 - 254
Anna Rykowska
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 255 - 278
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 297 - 300
Paweł Rojek
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 301 - 304
Małgorzata Cymorek
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 305 - 311
Anna Głąb
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 312 - 319
Immanuel Kant
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 5 - 22
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 39 - 56
Józef Gołuchowski
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 93 - 122
Stefan Zabieglik
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 123 - 149
Andrzej Leśniak
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 163 - 180
Niels Nymann Eriksen
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 193 - 208
Marcin Waligóra
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 225 - 238
Katarzyna Barska
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 239 - 254
Anna Rykowska
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 255 - 278
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 297 - 300
Paweł Rojek
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 301 - 304
Małgorzata Cymorek
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 305 - 311
Anna Głąb
Principia, Volume 35-36, 2003, pp. 312 - 319
Publication date: 2003
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Cezary Wodziński
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 17 - 28
Andrzej Leśniak
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 29 - 33
Herbert Schnädelbach
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 91 - 107
Leszek Brogowski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 109 - 127
Krzysztof Guczalski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 139 - 152
Piotr Łukowski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 169 - 184
Tomasz Żuradzki
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 195 - 200
Maciej Uliński
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 201 - 204
Maria Kostyszak
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 205 - 209
Ewa Czesna
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 211 - 216
Adam A. Dura
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 217 - 224
Tomasz Poller
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 225 - 231
Tomasz Żuradzki
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 195 - 200
Maciej Uliński
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 201 - 204
Maria Kostyszak
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 205 - 209
Ewa Czesna
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 211 - 216
Adam A. Dura
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 217 - 224
Tomasz Poller
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 225 - 231
Cezary Wodziński
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 17 - 28
Andrzej Leśniak
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 29 - 33
Herbert Schnädelbach
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 91 - 107
Leszek Brogowski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 109 - 127
Krzysztof Guczalski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 139 - 152
Piotr Łukowski
Principia, Volume 34, 2003, pp. 169 - 184
Publication date: 2002
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Michał Filipczuk
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 5 - 23
Mateusz Falkowski
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 77 - 105
Paweł Korobczak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 107 - 122
Marcin Karas
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 123 - 134
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 135 - 157
Piotr J. Przybysz
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 159 - 188
Jan Wawrzyniak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 189 - 207
Aleksandra Derra
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 209 - 223
Bartłomiej Świątczak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 225 - 243
Janusz Mączka
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 245 - 255
Ryszard Mordarski
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 257 - 265
Ryszard Mirek
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 267 - 270
Piotr Witek
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 271 - 278
Ryszard Mordarski
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 257 - 265
Ryszard Mirek
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 267 - 270
Piotr Witek
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 271 - 278
Michał Filipczuk
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 5 - 23
Mateusz Falkowski
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 77 - 105
Paweł Korobczak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 107 - 122
Marcin Karas
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 123 - 134
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 135 - 157
Piotr J. Przybysz
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 159 - 188
Jan Wawrzyniak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 189 - 207
Aleksandra Derra
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 209 - 223
Bartłomiej Świątczak
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 225 - 243
Janusz Mączka
Principia, Volume 32-33, 2002, pp. 245 - 255
Publication date: 2001
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editor:
Paweł Pieniążek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 37 - 58
Barbara Tuchańska
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 81 - 89
Janusz Kaczmarek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 99 - 115
Marek Rosiak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 117 - 133
Sebastian T. Kołodziejczyk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 145 - 158
Artur Banaszkiewicz
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 207 - 218
Ryszard Panasiuk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 219 - 236
Józef Piórczyński
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 237 - 253
Marek Kozłowski
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 255 - 272
Piotr Szałek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 273 - 294
Janusz Maciaszek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 295 - 303
Leon Miodoński
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 305 - 310
Agata Janaszczyk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 311 - 315
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 317 - 323
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 325 - 331
Jacek Rabus
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 333 - 335
Barbara Tuchańska
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 81 - 89
Janusz Kaczmarek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 99 - 115
Marek Rosiak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 117 - 133
Sebastian T. Kołodziejczyk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 145 - 158
Artur Banaszkiewicz
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 207 - 218
Ryszard Panasiuk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 219 - 236
Józef Piórczyński
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 237 - 253
Marek Kozłowski
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 255 - 272
Piotr Szałek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 273 - 294
Janusz Maciaszek
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 295 - 303
Leon Miodoński
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 305 - 310
Agata Janaszczyk
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 311 - 315
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 317 - 323
Andrzej W. Nowak
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 325 - 331
Jacek Rabus
Principia, Volume 30-31, 2001, pp. 333 - 335
Publication date: 2001
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Redakcja tomu: Bogusław Szubert
Jan Patočka
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 9 - 26
Czesław Głombik
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 27 - 47
Josef Krob
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 77 - 89
Katarzyna Slowikowá
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 194 - 197
Jan Hartman
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 198 - 200
Monika Blanka Florek
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 201 - 206
Dorota Sieniarska
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 207 - 212
Roman Bromboszcz
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 213 - 218
Ziemowit Cieślik
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 219 - 224
Jan Patočka
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 9 - 26
Czesław Głombik
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 27 - 47
Josef Krob
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 77 - 89
Katarzyna Slowikowá
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 194 - 197
Jan Hartman
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 198 - 200
Monika Blanka Florek
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 201 - 206
Dorota Sieniarska
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 207 - 212
Roman Bromboszcz
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 213 - 218
Ziemowit Cieślik
Principia, Volume 29, 2001, pp. 219 - 224
Publication date: 2000
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Nicolai Hartmann
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 7 - 63
Andrzej J. Noras
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 65 - 73
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 99 - 125
Przemysław Spryszak
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 187 - 208
Włodzimierz Heflik
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 209 - 227
Damian Leszczyński
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 231 - 246
Andrzej Zawadzki
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 247 - 269
Marcin Żurek
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 271 - 290
Adam Lipszyc
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 291 - 312
Helmut Walther
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 313 - 323
Dorota Plat
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 349 - 353
Agata Janaszczyk
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 355 - 359
Piotr Michalski
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 361 - 364
Artur Banaszkiewicz
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 365 - 368
Nicolai Hartmann
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 7 - 63
Andrzej J. Noras
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 65 - 73
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 99 - 125
Przemysław Spryszak
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 187 - 208
Włodzimierz Heflik
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 209 - 227
Damian Leszczyński
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 231 - 246
Andrzej Zawadzki
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 247 - 269
Marcin Żurek
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 271 - 290
Adam Lipszyc
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 291 - 312
Helmut Walther
Principia, Volume 27-28, 2000, pp. 313 - 323
Publication date: 2000
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Redakcja tomu: Andrzej Zalewski
Tomasz Majewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 23 - 33
Mirosław Przylipiak
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 35 - 53
Łucja Demby
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 55 - 70
Jacek Ostaszewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 71 - 97
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 99 - 128
Waldemar Frąc
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 129 - 148
Maciej Ożóg
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 149 - 157
Małgorzata Jakubowska
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 159 - 174
Wojciech Chyła
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 177 - 193
Krzysztof Loska
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 195 - 208
Tomasz Majewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 23 - 33
Mirosław Przylipiak
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 35 - 53
Łucja Demby
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 55 - 70
Jacek Ostaszewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 71 - 97
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 99 - 128
Waldemar Frąc
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 129 - 148
Maciej Ożóg
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 149 - 157
Małgorzata Jakubowska
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 159 - 174
Wojciech Chyła
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 177 - 193
Krzysztof Loska
Principia, Volume 26, 2000, pp. 195 - 208
Publication date: 1999
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Jacques Derrida
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 5 - 35
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 39 - 68
Michał Herer
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 69 - 92
Jakub Kloc-Konkołowicz
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 93 - 108
Jan Wadowski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 137 - 156
Bartosz Działoszyński
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 157 - 172
Paul Ricoeur
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 175 - 197
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 223 - 248
Tadeusz Zatorski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 251 - 267
Adam Chmielewski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 269 - 277
Katarzyna Morajko
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 279 - 288
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 289 - 299
Jacek Jaśtal
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 301 - 308
Jacques Derrida
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 5 - 35
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 39 - 68
Michał Herer
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 69 - 92
Jakub Kloc-Konkołowicz
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 93 - 108
Jan Wadowski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 137 - 156
Bartosz Działoszyński
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 157 - 172
Paul Ricoeur
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 175 - 197
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 223 - 248
Tadeusz Zatorski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 251 - 267
Adam Chmielewski
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 269 - 277
Katarzyna Morajko
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 279 - 288
Marek Drwięga
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 289 - 299
Jacek Jaśtal
Principia, Volume 24-25, 1999, pp. 301 - 308
Publication date: 1999
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editors: Alina Djakowska, Aldona Schiffmann
Niels Jørgen Cappelørn
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 11 - 23
Jon Stewart
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 25 - 42
Edward Kasperski
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 117 - 136
Andrzej Chojecki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 137 - 144
Hieronim Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 145 - 156
Wiesław Gromczyński
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 157 - 170
Antoni Szwed
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 171 - 184
Hieronim Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 185 - 192
Niels Jørgen Cappelørn
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 11 - 23
Jon Stewart
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 25 - 42
Edward Kasperski
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 117 - 136
Andrzej Chojecki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 137 - 144
Hieronim Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 145 - 156
Wiesław Gromczyński
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 157 - 170
Antoni Szwed
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 171 - 184
Hieronim Chojnacki
Principia, Volume 23, 1999, pp. 185 - 192
Publication date: 1998
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Franz Brentano
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 7 - 19
Nicolai Hartmann
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 21 - 56
Tadeusz Zatorski
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 77 - 108
Werner Strube
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 109 - 117
Marek Szulakiewicz
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 119 - 138
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 139 - 158
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 159 - 174
Piotr Mróz
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 193 - 207
Łukasz Stanek
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 209 - 223
Rodolfo Mondolfo
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 245 - 254
Geoffrey Stephen Kirk
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 255 - 259
Jacek Jaśtal
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 263 - 271
Sebastian Kołodziejczyk
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 273 - 287
Katarzyna Morajko
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 289 - 295
Ignacy S. Fiut
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 297 - 302
Jan Hartman
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 327 - 335
Franz Brentano
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 7 - 19
Nicolai Hartmann
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 21 - 56
Tadeusz Zatorski
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 77 - 108
Werner Strube
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 109 - 117
Marek Szulakiewicz
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 119 - 138
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 139 - 158
Piotr Mróz
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 193 - 207
Łukasz Stanek
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 209 - 223
Rodolfo Mondolfo
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 245 - 254
Geoffrey Stephen Kirk
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 255 - 259
Marek Kwiek
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 159 - 174
Jacek Jaśtal
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 263 - 271
Sebastian Kołodziejczyk
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 273 - 287
Katarzyna Morajko
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 289 - 295
Ignacy S. Fiut
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 297 - 302
Jan Hartman
Principia, Volume 21-22, 1998, pp. 327 - 335
Publication date: 1998
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Volume Editor: Janusz Mizera
Janusz Mizera
Principia, Volume 20, 1998, pp. 5 - 26
Publication date: 1997
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Immanuel Kant
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 7 - 15
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 17 - 48
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 71 - 94
Karol Polcyn
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 115 - 126
Tadeusz Czarnecki
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 157 - 181
Anna Sierszulska
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 183 - 195
Stanisław Łojek
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 207 - 223
Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 263 - 266
Gabriel Kurczewski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 267 - 271
Małgorzata Jantos
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 273 - 278
Immanuel Kant
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 7 - 15
Światosław Florian Nowicki
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 17 - 48
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 71 - 94
Karol Polcyn
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 115 - 126
Tadeusz Czarnecki
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 157 - 181
Anna Sierszulska
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 183 - 195
Stanisław Łojek
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 207 - 223
Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 263 - 266
Gabriel Kurczewski
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 267 - 271
Małgorzata Jantos
Principia, Volume 18-19, 1997, pp. 273 - 278
Publication date: 1996
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Krzysztof Matuszewski, Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 71 - 71
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 93 - 113
Adam Olech
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 153 - 179
Jacek Zieliński
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 181 - 197
Maciej Manikowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 199 - 217
Mariusz Turowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 219 - 239
Krzysztof Żółtański
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 241 - 253
Piotr Bukowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 255 - 264
Zbigniew Zalewski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 265 - 270
Krzysztof Matuszewski, Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 71 - 71
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 93 - 113
Adam Olech
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 153 - 179
Mariusz Turowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 219 - 239
Jacek Zieliński
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 181 - 197
Maciej Manikowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 199 - 217
Krzysztof Żółtański
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 241 - 253
Piotr Bukowski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 255 - 264
Zbigniew Zalewski
Principia, Volume 16-17, 1997, pp. 265 - 270
Publication date: 1995
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Bertrand Russell
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 9 - 30
Leszek Nowak
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 81 - 98
Piotr Przybysz
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 107 - 122
Krzysztof Brzechczyn
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 126 - 134
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 137 - 152
Marek Łagosz
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 153 - 176
Bertrand Russell
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 9 - 30
Leszek Nowak
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 81 - 98
Piotr Przybysz
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 107 - 122
Krzysztof Brzechczyn
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 126 - 134
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 137 - 152
Marek Łagosz
Principia, Volume 15, 1996, pp. 153 - 176
Publication date: 1994
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Mikołaj Olszewski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 39 - 55
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 129 - 162
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 163 - 187
Maciej Uliński
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 189 - 202
Dariusz Łukasiewicz
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 203 - 212
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 213 - 234
Jadwiga Wiatlewska
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 235 - 246
Mariusz Zemło
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 247 - 255
Adam Olech
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 269 - 273
Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 275 - 280
Kazimierz Ślęczka
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 283 - 290
Maria Kostyszak
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 291 - 298
Ingardenowska ontologia egzystyncji [Gregor Haflinger, Über Existenz: Die Ontologie Roman Ingardens]
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 299 - 301
Andrzej Zalewski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 129 - 162
Piotr Dehnel
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 163 - 187
Maciej Uliński
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 189 - 202
Dariusz Łukasiewicz
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 203 - 212
Piotr Łaciak
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 213 - 234
Jadwiga Wiatlewska
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 235 - 246
Mariusz Zemło
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 247 - 255
Adam Olech
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 269 - 273
Artur Przybysławski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 275 - 280
Kazimierz Ślęczka
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 283 - 290
Maria Kostyszak
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 291 - 298
Ingardenowska ontologia egzystyncji [Gregor Haflinger, Über Existenz: Die Ontologie Roman Ingardens]
Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
Principia, Volume 13-14, 1995, pp. 299 - 301
Publication date: 1994
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
Publication date: 1994
Editor-in-Chief: Jan Hartman
G.W.F. Hegel
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 1 - 32
Arthur Schopenhauer
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 5 - 30
Richard Rorty
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 85 - 104
Thomas Tymoczko
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 105 - 122
Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 123 - 128
Kazimierz Kowalewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 143 - 162
Andrzej Suszka-Fiedor
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 163 - 180
Gabriela Kurylewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 181 - 186
Dorota Prabucka
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 187 - 196
Dariusz Łukasiewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 197 - 206
G.W.F. Hegel
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 1 - 32
Arthur Schopenhauer
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 5 - 30
Richard Rorty
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 85 - 104
Thomas Tymoczko
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 105 - 122
Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 123 - 128
Kazimierz Kowalewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 143 - 162
Andrzej Suszka-Fiedor
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 163 - 180
Gabriela Kurylewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 181 - 186
Dorota Prabucka
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 187 - 196
Dariusz Łukasiewicz
Principia, Volume 10-11, 1994, pp. 197 - 206