FAQ
Logotyp Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego

Historia i przemiany topoi jako źródło renesansowej reformy dialektyki

Data publikacji: 2014

Terminus, 2014, Tom 16, Zeszyt 2 (31), s. 133 - 150

https://doi.org/10.4467/20843844TE.14.018.3562

Autorzy

Magdalena Ryszka-Kurczab
Uniwersytet Komisji Edukacji Narodowej w Krakowie
ul. Podchorążych 2, 30-084 Kraków, Polska
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4175-9414 Orcid
Wszystkie publikacje autora →

Tytuły

Historia i przemiany topoi jako źródło renesansowej reformy dialektyki

Abstrakt

The history and changes of topoi as an impulse for the renaissance reform of dialectic

The following article presents the most important stages in the history of dialectic in the light of the changes of the topoi theory, from Aristotle’s Topics and Rhetoric, to Cicero’s Topica, Boethius’s tractates (In Ciceronis topica and De topicis differentiis) to the Medieval tradition. The author explains the most important shifts in the nature and function of loci between the 4th c. BC and the 16th c. AD, which allows a better understanding of the reasons of the fierce criticism of dialectic by Renaissance humanists, such as Lorenzo Valla or Rudolf Agricola, as well as the attempts they made to reform it.
Aristotle is considered the first creator of topoi that he discussed in the Topics and the second book of the Rhetoric. The right context for understanding the function of loci is a dialectical disputation with its specificity. It seems that for Aristotle topoi were sources of arguments as well as sources of argumentation premises. He acknowledged topos in at least two ways: as a strategy for finding an argument that allows to win a dialectical discussion and as a rule of inference.
For the later tradition of loci Cicero’s and Boethius’s commentaries on Topics were significant. Cicero wrote his Topica for a lawyer, Gaius Trebarius Testa, and ignored the context of dialectical disputation that was so important for Aristotle. For Cicero, topos (or locus) is the seat of arguments (sedes argumentorum). Referring to Aristotle’s division of rhetorical modes of persuasion, Cicero divided loci into intrinsic and extrinsic topics. Loci seem to work as pigeon holes, general headings under which one should look for arguments. Following the Stoics, Cicero considered dialectic and rhetoric to be two parts of the general science of logos. He also adopted the Stoics’ conception of dialectic as ars bene disserendi and divided it into two parts: the finding of arguments, i.e. ratio inveniendi (topike), and the judging of them (ratio iudicandi).
Boethius, a crucial figure in the history of dialectic as a translator of Aristotle’s Organon, abandoned Cicero’s definition of topos as the seat of arguments and adopted Themistius’ (an early commentator on Aristotle) understanding of locus as a tool for justifying inference. Moreover, he identified topics with propositiones maximae, which are universal and well-known propositions that ‘need no proof (probation), but rather themselves provide proof for things that are in doubt’. Loci are also understood by Boethius to be genera of these universal and undoubted propositions (so called differentiae) and to contain them.
According to Boethius, loci are principles of demonstration, they guarantee the validity of an argument. Such approach distinctly subordinates the art of inventing an argument (inventio) to the art of justifying its conclusion (iudicium). Medieval logicians, such as Abelard, Petrus Juliani, Albert the Great, William Sherwood or Lambert of Auxerre, adopted Boethius’ rather than Cicero’s or Aristotle’s approach to the loci.
It was not until the Renaissance humanists tried to change the state of the matters, that projects of “new dialectic” were created. Humanists, such as Lorenzo Valla and Rudolf Argicola, aimed to rediscover the real meaning of Aristotle’s Topics and to broaden the way loci were used. Their efforts had a common source: the belief that scholastic dialectic was inadequate to what it was supposed to be in Aristotle’s view.

 

Bibliografia

Aristote, Les Topiques, wyd. i przeł. J. Brunschwig, Paris 1967.

Aristotle, The „Art” of Rhetoric, transl. by J.H. Freese, Cambridge 1990 (Loeb Classical Library).

Aristotle, The complete works of Aristotle. The revised Oxford translation, ed. J. Barnes, Princeton 1984.

Aristotle, Topica et Sophistici elenchi, transl. and notes by W.D. Ross, Oxford 1958.

Arystoteles, Retoryka, [w:] idem, Retoryka – Poetyka, przekł., wstęp i komentarz H. Podbielski, Warszawa 1988.

Arystoteles, Topiki, [w:] idem, Topiki – O dowodach sofistycznych, przekł., wstęp i komentarz K. Leśniak, Warszawa 1978.

Boethius, De Topicis differentiis, [w:] Patrologiae Latinae Cursus Completus. Series Latina, vol. 64, ed. J.P. Migne, Paris 1847.

Cicero, Academica, transl. by H. Rackman, Cambridge 1951 (Loeb Classical Library).

Cicero, De Inventione. Topica, transl. by H. M. Hubbel, Cambridge 1976 (Loeb Classical Library).

Cyceron, Topiki, [w:] idem, Pisma filozoficzne, t. IV, przeł. W. Kornatowski, komentarz i posłowie K. Leśniak, Warszawa 1963.

Cyceron, O mówcy, tłum., wstęp i komentarz B. Awianowicz, Kęty 2010.

Green-Pedersen N.J., The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages. The Commentaries on Aristotle’s and Boethius ‘Topics’, München–Wien 1984.

Jardin L., Lorenzo Valla and the Intellectual Origins of Humanist Dialectic, „Journal of the History of Philosophy” 15 (1977), s. 143–164.

Monfasani J., Lorenzo Valla and Rudolph Agricola, „Journal of the History of Philosophy” 28 (1990), s. 181–200.

de Pater W.A., Les Topiques d’Aristote et la dialectique platonicienne: la méthodologie de la definition, Fribourg 1965.

de Pater W.A., La fonction de lieu et de l’instrument dans les Topiques, [w:] Aristotle on Dialectic. Proceedings of the Third Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. G.E.L. Owen, Oxford 1968, s. 164–188.

Ryan E.E., Aristotle’s Theory of Rhetorical Argumentation, Montreal 1984.

Slomkowski P., Aristotle’s Topics, Leiden–New York–Köln 1997.

Spranzi M., The Art of Dialectic between Dialogue and Rhetoric: The Aristotelian Tradition, Amsterdam–Philadelphia 2011.

Stump E., Boethius’s ‘De topicis differentiis’, Ithaca 1978.

Informacje

Informacje: Terminus, 2014, Tom 16, Zeszyt 2 (31), s. 133 - 150

Typ artykułu: Oryginalny artykuł naukowy

Tytuły:

Polski:

Historia i przemiany topoi jako źródło renesansowej reformy dialektyki

Angielski:

The history and changes of topoi as an impulse for the renaissance reform of dialectic

Autorzy

https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4175-9414

Magdalena Ryszka-Kurczab
Uniwersytet Komisji Edukacji Narodowej w Krakowie
ul. Podchorążych 2, 30-084 Kraków, Polska
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4175-9414 Orcid
Wszystkie publikacje autora →

Uniwersytet Komisji Edukacji Narodowej w Krakowie
ul. Podchorążych 2, 30-084 Kraków, Polska

Publikacja: 2014

Status artykułu: Otwarte __T_UNLOCK

Licencja: Żadna

Udział procentowy autorów:

Magdalena Ryszka-Kurczab (Autor) - 100%

Korekty artykułu:

-

Języki publikacji:

Polski