Grzegorz Dziamski
Arts & Cultural Studies Review, Issue 1 (51) „Kulturowe praktyki współczesności”, 2022, pp. 127 - 147
https://doi.org/10.4467/20843860PK.22.009.15754Many aesthetic lecturers feel that the subject of their lectures is not so much aesthetics as the history of aesthetics, the aesthetic views of Plato and Aristotle, Kant and Hegel, Hume and Burke, British philosophers of taste and German romantics. Does this mean that aesthetics is nourished by its own past, nourished by reinterpretations of its classics, defends concepts and categories that no longer inspire anyone? Don’t they open up new cognitive perspectives? Does this mean that aesthetics is dead today, like Latin or Sanskrit, and that its vision of art and beauty is outdated, out of date and completely useless?
Stefan Morawski in the introduction to the anthology Twilight of Aesthetics – Alleged or Authentic? he wrote that he did not know the history of aesthetic thought that would begin in the eighteenth century with Baumgarten. Today we can meet with such an approach more and more often. Many authors assume that in the second half of the 18th century, modern aesthetics was born as a science of senses, how our higher (sight, hearing) and lower senses (taste, smell, touch) contribute to our knowledge of the world.
In the introduction to the anthology cited here, Stefan Morawski divides the history of aesthetics into four periods of unequal length. The Morawski diagram seems to be a convenient starting point for defining the changing object of aesthetics. The first of the periods distinguished by Morawski is the longest one, lasting from Ancient Greece to Enlightenment, can be called the history of aesthetic thought, the second is philosophical aesthetics, the third is a time of emancipation and institutionalization of aesthetics as autonomous discipline, and the fourth period leads beyond the limits of classical aesthetics.
Grzegorz Dziamski
Arts & Cultural Studies Review, Issue 2 (8), 2010, pp. 7 - 16
We have no problems with using the term ‘culture’ in such phrases as ‘Polish culture’,
‘German, French, British, Japanese culture’. In the sense assigned to the concept of culture by Johann Gotffried Herder at the end of the 18th century – culture is a way of life developed by some community (people, nation). But already in the case of the European culture, problem emerges. This is fully justified as for Herder the major element of culture, making it distinctive against other cultures, was language. Is the traditional Herder’s concept of culture (can be called sociological one) still useful in the contemporary world where the dominant figures are emigrants, refugees, tourists, urban wonderers, players? Should not we look for some other concept of culture assuming, as a starting point, that the concept of culture is not merely a descriptive concept but also an operational one and therefore has a significant impact upon our perception of the world and our activity in the world? In each culture we can identify three levels of enculturation: the deep level which naturalizes certain ways of thinking and behaving; social level – when the culture is experienced by individuals as symbolic violence; and finally the level which depends on individual choices, sometimes called a taste. This third level can be called art in opposition to culture. Art stands for whatever unique and original; culture – whatever collective and traditional. Art is the engine of culture. This dynamic aspect of culture was not reflected in Herder’s concept of culture, while this is the most important feature of today’s global culture prevailing in large cities where languages, habits and religions mix, where all, including native inhabitants, feel somewhat deprived of their roots and forced to search for new roots, and who become radicant people – artists who teach us how to live in today’s culture.